#title Ideograph freedom, the implicated body and coping with technology
#subtitle A rhetorical comparative analysis of Zen and the art of motorcycle maintenance and the Unabomber Manifesto
#author Blake E. Snyder
The University of Montana
#authors Blake E. Snyder
#date 2000
#source <[[https://scholarworks.umt.edu/etd/5225][scholarworks.umt.edu/etd/5225]]>
#lang en
#pubdate 2024-12-04T14:37:43
#topics analysis of Ted’s ideas & actions
#notes Graduate Student Theses. Recommended Citation: Snyder, Blake E., “Ideograph freedom the implicated body and coping with technology: A rhetorical comparative analysis of Zen and the art of motorcycle maintenance and the Unabomber Manifesto” (2000). Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers. 5225.
#rights This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at ScholarWorks at University of Montana. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks at University of Montana. For more information, please contact [[mailto:scholarworks@mso.umt.edu][scholarworks@mso.umt.edu]].
Permission is granted by the author to reproduce this material in its entirety, provided that this material is used for scholarly purposes and is properly cited in published works and reports.
Any copying for commercial purposes or financial gain may be undertaken only with the author’s explicit consent.
*** Title Page
Like Kaczynski, I worry about technology’s encroachments upon privacy and other cherished American freedoms ... Somewhat like Kaczynski, I have mixed feelings about the mixed blessings of technology.Theodore John Kaczynski, known by most of the general public as the “Unabomber,” pleaded guilty to a number of bombings sent through the mail between the years 1978 and 1995. His plea was announced on January 22nd, 1998. The trial itself received substantial media coverage. As Mello (1999) states, “Seventy-five news organizations congregated at ‘Club Ted,’ a parking lot near the Sacramento courtroom.” While much of the attention drawn to Kaczynski and the case was due to the fact that three people were killed and a number injured during his stint as the “Unabomber,” part of what captivated the general public as well as the media was both the man’s convictions and the man himself. Kaczynski had been a rather innocuous professor of mathematics at the prominent University of California at Berkeley before retreating to Montana and becoming a hermit. He received his degree in Mathematics from Harvard at the age of twenty. Most importantly, though, were his ideas concerning technology and modem society. They were Kaczynski’s justification for why he had become a serial bomber. Kaczynski’s arguments that technology has taken too much control over our lives and that a revolution against it (along with modem society) is necessary were first made public in June of 1995, when his Manifesto (1995) appeared in The Washington Post. Today, an Internet search of unabomber manifesto will pull between forty and fifty-thousand sites that either briefly mention the man, the case, the Manifesto, or discuss in detail his views regarding technology and society. Some websites even provide full texts of the 52-page Manifesto[1]. This thesis will examine technology as it gets discussed with respect to modern-day society. First, it is important to discuss the role of technology in society. “Technology” refers to a complex phenomenon which appears to be receiving more and more discussion with each new innovation that gets applied to the everyday world and the everyday lives of its inhabitants[2]. Borgmann (1984) describes technology as being the characteristic way in which we engage the world. Essentially, technology is presented as paradigmatic; it is focal to our reality. In other words, everything about our lives is either implicated within or has implications for the technological paradigm[3]. This requires further explication. For example, when we are at work, at home, on vacation, or engaged in a hobby, technology is ever-present. There do exist instances in which we are far removed from technological innovation. However, these situations are usually a response to technology. That is, we are making a choice to be removed from technology as best we can in order to “get away from it all.” If this were the case in 1984, it is certainly no less the case as we close out the century and prepare to enter a new one. For the purposes of this research, I will characterize technology’ more specifically as: a) a set of artifacts made by humans, b) an institution that includes the “engineering” and reshaping of our world, and c) an attitude. Naturally, one might expect there to be rather strong views concerning technology and its implications for modem-day society. Don Hide (1993) identifies five main arguments taken in response to the concerns over technology with respect to an issue that has come to the forefront in the 1990’s: the environment[4]. The first claims that modem technologies are still developing, and will evolve into more positive and refined technologies capable of handling environmental problems. The second argument advocates a “scale-down” approach to technology in general. Control has become too difficult via centralization. A more decentralized and smaller scale approach is what is needed. The third argument Ihde refers to as a more radical group of “alternative technology positions,” seeking alternative models for technologies in both understanding and context. Deep ecologists and ecofeminists fall within this group, he argues. The fourth and perhaps most extreme position Ihde labels the catastrophic position. Modem technologies are viewed to be no longer controllable, and are “run-away or autonomous.” Technology gets reified to a transcendental role, according to this argument. “Only a catastrophe of some sort could reverse the situation” (p. 92), as the idea of technology being “deterministic” can be taken as a synonym. The fifth and final position Ihde discusses, he calls the postmodernist position. It argues that modernity, “which includes the basic structures of technoscience, is already coming to an end.” That is, society is entering a different kind of reality, one which includes, among other things, the element of virtual reality. The economy is of special significance here. Information is now being regarded as the most precious resource, replacing the likes of coal, iron ore, plastics, etc. The postmodernist position rejects any return to past models as an outcome because the social struct ure of which we are a part possesses a natural tendency to move forward. This is not to say that information has to become our most precious resource of the future, but rather that we as a society, in moving forward, are choosing this to be so. Ted Kaczynski can be associated rather clearly with the catastrophic position Hide discusses. Kaczynski argues that technology takes the form of an over-arching “system,” whereby individuals are forced to function within the confines of the system’s demands and requirements. He maintains that the system limits individual autonomy, or freedom, and that the only way for the human species to re-capture the levels of autonomy that he argues were prevalent during the period of primitive man is to revolt against the technological system in such a mass, cohesive way as to extirpate all that constitutes modern-day society. For Kaczynski, this entails what can be perceived to be a catastrophe. This may be our only option, he asserts, for the path to human fulfillment has been occluded by technology and its ramifications. He argues that a catastrophe is preferred over the alternative future which, among other things, likely entails the genetic engineering of human beings. While Kaczynski can be identified with the catastrophic position, Robert Pirsig (1974) argues that we can, in fact, reconcile technology with modem society in such a way as to obviate such catastrophes. Pirsig, in his well-known work, Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance, assesses the problem of technology through individual terms. He argues that if, at the level of the individual, values are shifted to involve and ensure caring, gumption, and Quality (with a capital “Q”), feelings such as alienation and frustration that seem to be becoming more and more prominent in modern-day society will essentially be alleviated. The individual can find fulfillment if a re-orientation of values occurs. For Kaczynski, true fulfillment can only be acquired through a revolution against technology, not a reformation within it. The purpose of this research then is to examine the way two texts: Theodore Kaczynski’s Manifesto (sometimes referred to as the “Unabomber Manifesto”) and Robert Pirsig’s Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance, choose to discuss the phenomenon of technology with respect to society. It is important to stress that I am examining representations of the phenomenon of technology. In other words, explored here is how Pirsig and Kaczynski first represent the phenomenon, and then argue for how we as a society ought to cope with it given modern-day structure. What follows is a discussion of why these two texts are being chosen as part of the present inquiry into the phenomenon of technology. *** Discussing Technology The first and most obvious reason for selecting these texts is that they both address the phenomenon of technology. More importantly, though, is that both artifacts discuss the phenomenon as a whole, rather than examining only certain aspects of it. In other words, instead of looking at how one particular technological innovation is utilized, incorporated into society, or influential, Pirsig and Kaczynski choose to examine technology in general, and how this phenomenon as a whole is to be coped with in our society. That is, both authors treat technology as a material, social, and psychological institution. While a discussion of this magnitude has the potential to become unclear and inaccurate, being so far-reaching and ambitious, one cannot help but feel these types of discussions are more significant and meaningful with regards to how we live our lives each day (presuming the discussions are presented well). Both Pirsig and Kaczynski wrestle with technology, and wind up with completely different “recommendations” for how we as a society ought to deal with the reality it has created for us. **** Different means for reconciliation Although Pirsig and Kaczynski both address the phenomenon of technology, they do so in different ways, as I’ve briefly already mentioned. Kaczynski argues that the “system,” described as technological society and the constraints technology has imposed upon the individual, has taken autonomy and the fulfilling life away from the individual. For example, he argues: “...in our society the effort needed to satisfy the biological needs has been reduced to triviality. More importantly, in our society people do not satisfy their biological needs AUTONOMOUSLY but by functioning as parts of an immense social machine” (p. 8). The only way one is to procure for him/herself the kind of freedom associated with the fulfilling life as s/he sees it is by mass revolt against modem society. Kaczynski concedes that this will be catastrophic to a certain degree. Individuals will have to endure a harsh period of adjustment toward more primitive ways. However, he claims it to be better than the projected alternative, arguing that things will only get worse the longer the collective unit of society waits to revolt. Pirsig on the other hand believes that if the individual re-orients his/her values to place a higher emphasis on caring gumption, and Quality in one’s work, hobbies... etc., then progress can be made toward a reconciliation of technology with society. Pirsig writes:(Mello, 1999, p. 20)
Believe me, when the world is seen not as a duality of mind and matter but as a trinity of quality, mind, and matter, then the art of motorcycle maintenance and other arts take on a dimension of meaning they never had. The spector of technology ... becomes not an evil but a positive, fun thing, (p. 221)Unlike Kaczynski, who claims the problem of technology has transcended individual levels to reach more systemic ones, Pirsig assesses the problem at the individual level, arguing that it is at this level where goals must be set and progress can be made. In other words, people can find fulfillment, even within modem society, if they reflect on and follow their individual values. Both Kaczynski and Pirsig agree that technology has at least reduced for the individual what is perceived to be a fulfilling lifestyle. That is, living in a technologically- developed society has left people with, at least sometimes, feelings of frustration toward and alienation from the society in which they live. Both argue that freedom, or autonomy, is limited in such a society. Yet, the two authors not only assess the problem in different terms (or on different levels), but proceed into completely different recommendations for how we as a society ought to cope with technology. Additionally, the two texts are disparate in terms of time (Pirsig’s was published in 1974, Kaczynski’s was made public in 1995), purpose, style, and audience. By analyzing both texts, I will provide a more thorough conceptualization of the phenomenon of technology. As mentioned, technology is a complex phenomenon, one with a broad scope and many viewpoints concerning the ways it should be approached. The analysis presented here examines two of these viewpoints, delineating how they are similar and different in the way each structures its argument. *** One Cultural Artifact and One with Potential Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance is certainly a cultural artifact. Since its publication in 1974, it has sold more than three million copies worldwide. Consequently, it has “reached” the public at-large, far beyond the academic circle. Pirsig (1974) notes in the ten-year afterward of the text that the book was submitted to 122 publishers, and only one picked it up. Of course, one is all you need. He goes on to note that the publisher offered him a standard nominal fee, and that he probably shouldn’t expect anything more. However, the end result was quite different. Soon after the book’s release, critical acclaim followed. This led to numerous television and radio interviews, along with multiple lecture invitations (Pirsig, 1974). There have been many a discussion of Quality in cities other than Bozeman, Montana, no doubt[5]. Pirsig’s discussion of technology and Quality is a complex one, and it is a tribute to both his writing style and the nature of the discussion itself that it has been so well received. While its acceptance in the academic circle is seen as appropriate, it is probably surprising even to Pirsig that it has been so embraced by the mainstream. Kaczynski’s Manifesto is not considered to be a cultural artifact — at least not yet. Nor has Kaczynski acquired the type of reverence bestowed upon Pirsig. Part of the reason the Manifesto is not and may never be a cultural artifact is that most of the American public conjecturally desires to condemn Kaczynski’s message because of the evil of the messenger. While both Pirsig and Kaczynski employ rhetorical means in attempting to persuade audiences through their texts, it is Kaczynski that also employs non-rhetorical means when he murders individuals in an effort to create a more powerful and lasting message. Thus, many may dismiss an analysis of the Manifesto simply on the claim that he is a “nutcase.” However, this claim must be attached to its proper place. While few would disagree Kaczynski was wrong in his extreme course of action and probably even crazy, the Manifesto, when taken on its own merit, presents some interesting arguments, ones which even Michael Mello (1999) is compelled to agree with (see passage at beginning of this paper). Mello is a former defense attorney and current anti-capital punishment activist. He is not the only one identifying with at least some parts of the Manifesto. The fact that there are so many web-sites out there addressing Kaczynski, the Manifesto, or both, suggests that people are at least discussing the viewpoint he presents[6]. Many of the sites do disagree with Kaczynski, citing the dubious nature of some of his predictions, but there are also many advocating the kind of action he calls for. Kaczynski has captured much attention outside of the academic circle, while echoing noted philosophy of technology scholars such as Ellul (1964) and Marcuse (1968). Ellul argues that a technological society cannot be civilized, and its end is not freedom, but the opposite of freedom. By this he means that for all the liberation technology is supposed to provide, it in fact imposes more constraints upon the individual. These constraints, taking the form of trivialities for which we are forced to hold ourselves accountable to, reduce our levels of freedom. For example, in modern-day society it is not uncommon for individuals to possess multiple forms of communication, such as electronic mail, pagers, fax machines, and cellular phones. We are expected to respond to messages that we receive through these mediums. In this regard, it is a burden for us to be held accountable for so many forms of communication. This is not to say that we do not appreciate being so accessible, and being able to access others when we need to. Rather, it is that by their very nature we are constrained by all of these communication mediums because they force us to be responsible for them. Marcuse gets precisely at Kaczynski’s claim that humans cannot properly engage the power process in a technological setting (this will be further explicated in the next section) when he argues that in such a society, all basic needs (food, clothing, shelter, health) are satisfied, and only non-necessary needs become the goal. Thus, individuals only indirectly provide for their vital needs. This is accomplished usually through a job of some sort, where one works to earn money, and then uses this money to procure for oneself food, clothing, shelter...etc. The “procuring for oneself’ these vital needs, though, is all too often accomplished through others. For example, we allow others to build our homes; we purchase clothing from department stores that was made by individuals other than ourselves; and we often buy pre-cooked or pre-prepared food from supermarkets (this does not include meals we eat at restaurants or fast-food chains). As a result of not being able to directly provide for our vital needs, we set goals that reflect materialistic needs, such as a bigger home, a nicer car, or a larger salary. The preceding comments appear to justify an inquiry into the Manifesto, particularly when analyzed alongside an “opposing” text, such as Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance. What must be taken up in what follows is a more in-depth discussion of the texts at hand. Additionally, the structure and style of each text will be examined. Differences and similarities will be addressed in more detail in this section. The fact that these two texts are separated by approximately twenty years is not to be overlooked. However, that Kaczynski is being discussed and Pirsig is still being discussed also are important points. Both texts are worthy artifacts for analysis regarding the phenomenon of technology in society. Consequently, the following research questions are posed:
Perhaps he would have gone in the direction I’m now about to go in if this second wave of crystallization, the meta-physical wave, had finally grounded out where I’ll be grounding it out, that is, in the everyday world. I think metaphysics is good if it improves everyday life; otherwise forget it. But unfortunately for him it didn’t ground out. It went into a third mystical wave of crystallization from which he never recovered, (p. 221)The narrator, in attempting to reconcile Quality with technology, while at the same time attempting to avoid plummeting into the abyss which captured Phaedrus, addresses the split between the classical and romantic minds. Classical thinkers, regarding technology, want to know the intricate details of a device. Using Pirsig’s example of the motorcycle, “classics” aim to know everything about the bike: how the parts work together, what goes where, and generally, how the bike manages to operate. “Romantics” are less concerned with the components of the bike. They just appreciate it for the ride it offers the enthusiast. Pirsig argues that to arrive at Quality, it is necessary to create a kind of marriage between the classical and romantic styles. If we take the time to both appreciate and understand technology, or our jobs, or hobbies, or how these utilize technologies, he would argue, we can avoid much of the alienating and frustrating sentiments that characterize John and Sylvia. Doing this requires caring on the individual’s part; caring about their work, their hobbies, the technological innovations they incorporate into their lives...etc[9]. Caring is linked to the concept of gumption, in that they both involve the individual merging the concepts of “self ’ and “object.” Gumption is more specifically defined as “initiative,” or “common sense actively applied to real life.” For Pirsig, gumption has similar connotations. In motorcycle maintenance, it is “the psychic gasoline that keeps the whole thing going.” (p. 273). So instead of separating oneself from one’s work or hobby, one ought to perceive the two as a working relationship, or partnership. By this Pirsig simply means that too often individuals feel separated from tasks they are doing or objects they engage. He argues that, essentially, these tasks and objects are human creations, and should be perceived as being more connected to individuals than they are given credit for. Once this connection is achieved (Zen Buddhist philosophy has as one of its primary tenets the aspiration for “oneness”), the individual is fully engaged with a task or object. By being fully engaged with these and appreciating them, things not only get done, but they get done better than if the individual did not feel connected to them. Pirsig isolates what he calls “gumption traps,” of which there are two types: setbacks and hang-ups. A set-back would involve, for example, not having the right parts before you while working on your motorcycle. A hang-up could include variables like boredom and anxiety. These “traps” can deter one from achieving gumption, and subsequently, Quality. In pursuing Quality, the individual might carefully place all parts before him/her on sheets of newspaper and carefully take notes on the sequential process of removing and adding parts to the motorcycle. Additionally, should boredom or anxiety set in, Pirsig advocates taking some time off from the maintenance process in order to clear one’s head. Pirsig suggests that these sorts of steps are how one can come to grips with technology (and modem society) via Quality. Ted Kaczynski’s Manifesto is far less receptive to the phenomenon of technology than Robert Pirsig’s work. The Manifesto is approximately 52 pages in length and is structured as follows. Kaczynski begins by briefly discussing the negative consequences of the Industrial Revolution. In this introduction, he sets forth the following claim:
We do outline in a very general way the measures that those who hate the industrial system should take in order to prepare the way for a revolution against that form of society. This is not a political revolution. Its object will be to overthrow not governments but the economic and technological basis of the present society, (p. 1)The next section addresses the “Psychology of Modem Leftism,” and is a strategic move on his part, first to define what leftism is, and then to isolate his movement from it. He then moves into defining the power process and surrogate activities, and how these are at the root of social problems. He follows that with a discussion on the motives of scientists, and how this relates to a surrogate activity. Next, he discusses the nature of freedom, and how its restriction is unavoidable in an industrial society. Technology gets deemed a more powerful social force than the aspiration for freedom. Finally, Kaczynski discusses how revolution is “easier” than reform, and how to go about strategically instigating such a revolution, stating that this will not occur overnight, but will take some time for enough people to support the position that the present system must be abolished. Human beings possess a need for what Kaczynski calls the power process. The power process has four elements to it: goal, effort, attainment of goal, and autonomy. While the first three are fairly rudimentary, the fourth requires some qualification. Autonomy is related to individual effort toward goals. Individuals’ efforts must be undertaken on their own initiative and must be under their own control. Autonomy can be viewed as being closely related to the notion of freedom. When individuals are not autonomous in their decision-making (at least to some degree), they often feel as though their freedom is restricted. He later goes on to tie this into what he perceives as technology’s stripping of individual autonomy and freedom. Unlike many theorists who discuss power, Kaczynski does not directly associate the concept with an assertion of influence by one individual over another in some form of social relationship. Rather, he directs his discussion of power inward at the level of the individual, arguing that humans have a need to be able to control their own lives, in a sense. Kaczynski argues that in modem society this ability to “have control” over one’s own life is substantially limited as a result of technology. This relates to Lukes’ (1974) discussion of power, wherein one dimension (Lukes develops three) entails a community or disadvantaged group that does not know its own best interests. Kaczynski suggests that the individuals which constitute modem society do not know their own best interests. The result of this is an improper engagemenTOf the power process and a reliance upon surrogate activities as a means to procure fulfillment. Kaczynski mandates that the power process ought to only be associated with primary or real goals. These types of goals include fulfilling only those vital needs for survival, such as food, clothing, and shelter. It is important to note that in general modem society has made the attainment of these goals easy and trivial, according to Kaczynski. Thus, the power process does not get engaged in any proper and significant manner. The antithesis of the primary goal is the surrogate activity. Kaczynski explains: “We use the term ‘surrogate activity’ to designate an activity that is directed toward an artificial goal that people set up for themselves merely in order to have some goal to work toward, or let us say, merely for the sake of the ‘fulfillment’ that they get from pursuing the goal”(p. 7)[10]. Although it does not explicitly state it, it can be assumed that a job or a hobby would constitute a surrogate activity, as they do not satisfy any of the vital needs in a manner which engages the power process properly, according to Kaczynski. *** Stylistic Similarities and Differences With respect to style, Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance and the Manifesto can be considered similar in the way they present arguments concerning technology (“concerning technology” being the key clause here). Both Pirsig and Kaczynski adopt rational approaches in presenting their respective views on how technology ought to be reconciled with society. Structurally, they are similar in that both proceed by isolating why it is they feel technology is problematic, followed by how we as a society ought to solve this problem. But stylistically, both are also similar in that they present their approaches to technology and society as being rational, logical steps to make given the problem as they discuss it[11]. Consequently, rationality is understood here as the reason-based, logical attempt at understanding in general and progress specifically. It involves the view that reason and experience rather than nonrational means are the fundamental criteria in the solution of problems. It is also important to add that rationality is to some extent socially constructed, and in this respect a function of perspective and framing. Kaczynski makes the following argument: “A reform movement merely offers to solve a particular social problem. A revolutionary movement offers to solve all problems at one stroke and create a whole new world...” (p. 27), and “...the bigger the system grows, the more disastrous the consequences of its breakdown will be...” (p. 33). Pirsig offers the following assertion:
Thus, if the problem of technological hopelessness is caused by absence of care, both by technologists and anti-technologists; and if care and Quality are external and internal aspects of the same thing, then it follows logically that what really causes technological hopelessness is absence of the presence of Quality in technology by both technologists and anti-technologists, (p. 247–8)The fact that both Pirsig and Kaczynski present rational arguments regarding technology and society seems to be overshadowed, though, by the evident distinction between Kaczynski’s more scientific style and Pirsig’s more poetic approach. While both authors present rational arguments for how to approach technology, the difference is that, for Kaczynski, this constitutes his entire text. The Manifesto is scientific and argumentative, in that each section of the text specifically addresses the ills of technology as he sees it and how we as a society ought to respond to such ills[12]. For example, Kaczynski asserts:
In this article we give attention to only some of the negative developments that have grown out of the industrial-technological system ... we do outline in a very general way the measures that those who hate the industrial system should take in order to prepare the way [sic] for a revolution against that foim of society. (P- 1)Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance, however, has more than one theme, as mentioned. While one theme to the book is certainly rational in its discussion of technology, the other is much more poetic through its narrative of the father and son on a cross-country motorcycle trip. An example of the interplay between these two themes can be seen in the following passage:
The sky over the other wall of the canyon has become overcast, and the wind in the pines around us has become cool and ominous.It is this poetic element that seems to dominant the text, even in the way Pirsig glides back and forth between narrative and intellectual framework (and his discussion of Phaedrus within the two). This distinction will become more apparent and relevant in a later discussion of the ways in which “the body” is implicated by both in their evaluations of the technological society. What is now needed is a contextual analysis of how technology and society is being discussed/evaluated in the American culture. I will turn my attention specifically to relevant newspaper and magazine articles and/or editorials in an attempt to situate these two texts within their appropriate contexts.
At least the coolness makes it easier hiking ... I was talking about the first wave of crystallization outside rhetoric that resulted from Phaedrus’ refusal to define Quality. He had to answer the question, If you can’t define it, what makes you think it exists? (p. 193)
The spreading shortages were wrenching the way millions of Americans live and think. They now had to plan ahead. No more simply dropping into a service station when the fuel gauge was low; instead, many motorists were getting down to the stations the first thing in the morning to fill up their tanks. (“Summer”, 1973, p. 70)The solutions to the energy crisis would have a significant effect on the American lifestyle.[13] It became apparent that “Consumers inescapably will see their bills for electricity, heating, and gasoline raised ever higher — and they could conceivably find these necessities being rationed” (“Americas Energy”, 1973). In addition to the fuel and energy crisis, less abundant food supplies on grocery store shelves had its impact on the American consumer:
Americans had already changed their eating habits as meat prices soared and supplies grew tight....With other food items — poultry, dairy, and flour products — now running short, housewives might start grabbing things off supermarket shelves not because they need them at the moment, but for fear that they will not be available later on. (“Summer”, 1973, p. 70)The food shortage contributed to a penny-pinching lifestyle for the consumer. A high cost of eating is something that hit home everyday for the average American, no doubt (“High Cost”, 1973). In fact, the average family food bill had risen dramatically in recent years as well as throughout the year of 1973 (“High Cost”, 1973). Some were forced to seek cheaper alternatives to daily food staples. For example, something as common as a gallon of milk had to be replaced with the more inexpensive instant, nonfat dry milk (Letters, 1973a). All of these factors contributed to what many would consider an economic “devil term”: inflation. Inflation had actually nudged the Watergate affair aside on the front pages of newspapers and news magazines across the country (“Other”, 1973). Indeed, “folks....were more concerned about high prices than high crimes in the administration” (p. 22). Many will recall the not-so-catchy theme adopted by Nixon’s replacement for the presidency, Gerald Ford: WIN, or “Whip Inflation Now,” in 1975. These factors would translate into a more economically conscious consumer. An example of this can be seen in the push for more practical, inexpensive, and environmentally friendly automobiles that occurred in 1975. As a result of this, major auto companies in Detroit “scaled down” their automobile models, releasing a series of compact, fuel efficient, and less costly vehicles. These were a sharp contrast to what had been the norm for the American industry up until that point: big, powerful, fuel guzzling vehicles (“Detroit’s Gamble”, 1975). Many consumers praised the move, recognizing the economic benefits of the new line of automobiles (Forum, 1975). While the American consumer was forced to adjust to the changing economic climate during the early and mid-1970s, other issues would surface that speak to the growing frustration being experienced. An issue pertaining to Pirsig’s call for a reassessment of individual values is what one article appropriately termed “The Job Blahs” (“Job”, 1973). The discussion here is on the workplace, and how both blue-collar and white-collar workers feel alienated from their jobs, and/or find little to no fulfillment in them. As one steelworker is cited as stating, “it’s a boring, repetitious job — nasty, hot, and dirty work. I go there ‘cause I have to” (p. 79). Another autoworker is quoted as saying, “Everyday, for eight hours, we fight that black devil-chain [the assembly line]” (p. 79). The article attempts to capture the national sentiment regarding this issue:
The mood of this vast work force is obviously of tremendous importance to the country as a whole as well as to the individuals themselves. Worker attitudes affect productivity ... While people have been complaining about work since it was invented, there is a widespread feeling that there is something different about today’s discontent, (p. 79)The article categorizes these types of modern-day workers as:
the new problem children of the American economy: the “alienated” workers, afflicted with the blue-collar blues, the white-collar woes and the just plain on- the-job blahs. They are bored, rebellious, frustrated; sometimes they’re drunk on the job or spaced out on drugs, (p. 79)Nineteen million part-time or full-time workers were, at this time, engaged in manufacturing, “and one million of these are tied to the dull, routine tedium of an assembly line....” (p. 79). If consumers are frustrated with the quality of products produced by technological means, this seems to offer at least one reason why such a lack of quality exists. If workers don’t care about the work they’re doing, terms like “quality” and “the final product” don’t enter into the equation. Some individuals blame the structure of society for the alienation workers feel from their jobs, highlighting the transition from school to the work force:
If for twelve years a person is subjected to a situation where emphasis is placed on the individual, on personal freedom and accomplishment, it’s no wonder that when that person faces a situation where the emphasis is on the system, boredom, disillusionment and alienation result. (Letters, 1973b, p. 4).The lack of enthusiasm many workers felt for their jobs coupled with the poor quality of manufactured products appears to have been at the heart of much of the discontent individuals felt for technology and its byproducts. Whitman (1973) writes of the yearning for the past he experiences. It is his claim that things were simply done better before technological gadgetry stepped up to the forefront. He opens his essay by stating: “ ‘Nothing’s like it used to be,’ a friend exclaimed the other day when a plastic-handle screwdriver came apart in his hands.’ ” (p. 15). At the same time, however, others acknowledge that while there does exist some shabbiness in present-day craftsmanship, the obvious benefits technology has procured should not simply be swept under the rug (Letters, 1973c). American consumers were also concerned over the general safety of many of the products out on the market during this period. As one article reports (“Home Hazards”, 1973), “Each year at least 30 million Americans are hurt and 30,000 killed because of unsafe consumer products other than autos.” (p. 91). Part of the problem associated with these products is the way consumers choose to use them (such as playground equipment, bicycles, cleaning and lighting fluids...etc). However, this did not seem to quiet the overall public outcry. The Consumer Product Safety Commission was set up by Congress to evaluate many common household products and create safety standards (“Home Hazards”, 1973). The early and mid-1970s presented some interesting discussions concerning technology and its interplay with society. While the same can be said of the 1990’s, the difference lies in -what specifically that discussion is about. Worthy of mention is that the pace of life has greatly accelerated for most people in industrialized societies since the 1970s. The advent of digital electronics in general, and computer technology more specifically, has provided this more recent decade with a new set of topics open for discussion. This particular period more adamantly seeks to address the question of where technology is taking us (or perhaps leading us). *** The 1990s As with the 1970s, it is important to preface the current analysis with a brief discussion of Ted Kaczynski’s primary argument in his Manifesto (1995). Kaczynski argues that human beings in modem society do not fulfill the power process in any meaningful way. Instead of meeting one’s vital needs for survival in an autonomous manner, the individual relies on the “system,” or current-day structure of society, to procure these needs for him/her. In an attempt to make one’s life fulfilling, he argues that individuals engage in surrogate activities, such as a job or hobby, but that these activities do not fulfill for the individual vital needs (food, clothing, shelter...etc) in an autonomous way. Kaczynski asserts that if the technological system is not brought down by a mass revolution, it will grow so powerful that it will become unstoppable, and limitations to human autonomy such as the genetic engineering of individuals will become the norm. Elmer-Dewitt reported in 1993 that a debate had ensued over the issue of cows being treated with genetically engineered hormones in order to produce more milk for a growing society. We as consumers had relatively little say in the matter, except for those of us living in rural areas who had access to more “natural” milk (i.e., that which was produced by untreated cows). The National Institute of Health and the Food and Drug Administration assured consumers that there are no safety hazards associated with milk from cows that had been treated (Elmer-Dewitt, 1993c). Despite this, the sentiment loomed that this was just one of the products of living in a largely populated, growing society. Consumers were, for the most part, forced to adhere to production methods such as the one mentioned in order to sustain our society. These types of production methods such as the one just mentioned were a sign of an ever-growing population. Linden reported (1993) that the world was “about to pass a milestone: more people will live in urban areas than in the countryside” (pp. 28–29). While urban life has provided societies with many benefits, its shortcomings are a relevant topic for discussion: “A walk through the South Bronx fulfills every outsider’s vision of urban decline” (p. 35). Some respond to this issue by isolating over-population as the most pressing problem, while others argue that a lack of proper planning by local governments is where the fault lies (Linden, 1993). Bonfante (1993) discusses the trend of many Americans to pack up and move from the metropolises of the east and west coasts to the Rocky Mountains of Montana, Idaho, Wyoming, Colorado, Utah and New Mexico. Deedee Corradini, mayor of Salt Lake City, was reported as saying, “Look at L.A. or San Francisco. I don’t know how you can begin to solve those problems, whereas we can solve ours. Our problems are smaller.” (p. 23). The appeal of the “mountain cities” wasn’t simply its natural landscape. Its lure also involved the qualities of less crime, fewer inhabitants, and less stress. This appeal has no doubt created tension between some residents of mountain cities and visitors from the coasts. While some mountain residents simply ask visitors to adjust to the lifestyle rather than try to re-shape mountain life into city life (Letters, 1993e), others are more adamant in their hostility:
Invasion of high-end money earners has spoiled this area for those who have lived here for generations, forcing the natives to deal with higher real-estate prices, higher taxes and ruination of the environment. You can’t expect to accommodate this immigration without tapping into water, land, air, and other resources that sustain life. (Letters, 1993e, p. 8)Just as urban development and its ramifications were receiving significant discussion, so too was the area of specific technological innovations. The early 1990s began to see highly significant developments in digital/wireless communications and the computer industry. Elmer-Dewitt (1993b) discusses the “electronic superhighway,” and how the advent of the Internet will lead to a consolidation of home-office mediums, such as the television, telephone, and fax machine. The expectation is that the individual will essentially be able to do more while doing less. While many welcome the prospects of technological innovation, others have suspicions, claiming that such innovation will lead to an invasion of privacy, this since a record of what individuals do through these mediums will be stored electronically (Letters, 1993c). Some hold that modem technology will turn us into “couch potatoes,” as the evil behind such innovation is idleness (Letters, 1993c). Cyber cultures began to emerge as a result of this technological innovation (Elmer- Dewitt, 1993a). Its offspring, the cyberpunk, receives its name from cybernetics (“the science of communication and control theory”) and punk (“an antisocial rebel or hoodlum”) (p. 59). Elmer-Dewitt characterizes cyberpunk culture as “a way of looking at the world that combines an infatuation with high-tech tools and a disdain for conventional ways of using them” (p. 59). Virtual reality equipment is a favorite innovation of the cyberpunk. The frightening nature of cyber culture comes through in one San Jose State University mathematician’s characterization of the cyberpunk as being nothing less than the fusion of humans and machines (Elmer-Dewitt, 1993a). The idea of individuals becoming so involved with computers and so uninvolved with non-electronic devices casts eerie suspicions within many. For these respondents, the dehumanizing and unhealthy attributes associated with cyber culture are enough to repel them. Two more recent articles suggest that criticism of computer technology continues to profilerate. Chapman (2000) reveals that increasing numbers of computer experts are challenging corporations which try to lock down the internet and secure it for commerce. These “anti-corporation” groups are proponents of open source software and an open internet. They oppose an internet absorbed into mass culture, and they do not wish to see corporate logos on every web-site. Joy (2000) reveals the potential for an even bleaker scenario to unfold. Cofounder and chief scientist of Sun Microsystems, Joy argues that technological advances in the computer industry and beyond (e.g., genetic engineering) may prove to actually threaten the human species. Not surprisingly, Joy references Kaczynski’s Manifesto, and argues that increased levels of monitoring and perhaps even restriction are necessary to ensure that technology does not proceed so rapidly that it surpasses human capabilities to manage it effectively. Technological development in the computer and communications industries would receive much more discussion in a special edition of The New York Times Magazine (NYTM) published in September of 1997. The edition features a slew of articles devoted to current trends in technological innovation, and how these trends will alter our lives, for better and for worse. Examples of these include Krugman’s (1997) “The Paper Bag Revolution.” This piece de-emphasizes all of the mega-expensive, high-tech gadgetry and instead brings to the foreground the ways in which technology makes our lives easier (e.g., the way the Internet can be used in a non-glamorous way to locate certain things such as the nearest version of a particular department store). Another piece, entitled, “Addicted to Speed,” by James Gleick (1997), discusses the ways movies and televisions are getting faster with respect to the imagery they can present and the imagery that gets presented. Gleick notes in the trailer: “We love the sensation they give us, which is just as well — we couldn’t slow them down if we wanted to” (pp. 54–55). He suggests that, while it is fine that we appreciate this innovation, it is also important to acknowledge the rapid pace at which such innovation is occurring. One final piece worth noting is Elizabeth Royte’s (1997) article, “Life as We’ll Know it.” This article examines some of technological innovations that may surface in the near future. One example of this is the electronic book, which can hold a million volumes of say, the Library of Congress in its database. All one needs to do is scroll up or down to whatever it is one is searching for, and it is presented for them on screen. The NYTM received a substantial amount of feedback in the form of letters. They note at the beginning of the “Letters” (1997) section:
Our special issue on technology drew mail from scores of readers traveling at all speeds on the information superhighway. Technophiles were outnumbered, 4 to 1, by technophobes, who hold tight to rotary phones and complain that their children don’t visit friends anymore, except in chat rooms (p. 20).Though one should be careful not to overgeneralize, it does seem significant that so many responses were from “technophobes,” as they are labeled; those who aren’t so merrily jumping on board the information superhighway. It suggests that there appears to be a substantial amount of caution among the public regarding where all of this innovation is headed. Indeed, many echo what Kaczynski would argue about these types of innovations: that they strip the individual of even more autonomy than is necessary by “allowing” us to rely on them in our daily lives.. As such, they do more harm than good. One response is offered here:
Computer technology may be making people richer and life faster, but I’m not sure it’s making us smarter. Is it smart to become more alienated from one another, to exchange human relationships for frenetic speed and isolation?Keep this up and psychiatrists will reap untold profits (Letters, 1997, p. 20). Obviously, this individual is not prepared to risk the loss of one precious commodity for the acquisition of another: namely, sacrificing human relationships and “smarts,” for greater alienation and more speed in technology. Others weren’t so critical of the perceived progress, stating that these innovations were improvements, and we as a society ought to be ready to jump on the technological bandwagon (Letters, 1997). By in large, however, responses to the special edition on technology were more characteristic of a “technophobic” position. The following passages serves to illustrate this:
I don’t have to fake having a rotary phone; I have one. The best part is when people who are completely familiar with computers come over and have to ask for help using the phone. I love it. (pp. 27–28)The “plight of the technophobes” is in response to technological development within modern-day society. Wright (1995) discusses the efforts of evolutionary psychologists to examine the mismatch between our genetic makeup as a species and the modem world. The hope is to locate the source of discontent resting within many individuals. The timing of his piece leads to a reference to the Unabomber (Kaczynski had not been identified as the mail bomber at this point), and Wright mentions that: “There’s a little bit of the Unabomber in most of us. We may not share his approach to airing a grievance, but the grievance itself feels familiar” (p. 50). The argument Kaczynski sets forth and evolutionary psychologists are attempting to analyze is that modem society requires individuals to live under conditions that are drastically different from those by which the human race evolved (Wright, 1995). While some are content to reside in modem-day society, others acknowledge the depression that plagues so many as a moral stand, “a protest against a world we do not understand.” (Letters, 1995, p. 18). In other areas of society, advances in the field of genetics signal precisely the kind of trend Kaczynski warns his readers about. Thompson (1993) reports on Cynthia Cutshall and Ashanthi Desilva, two children afflicted with Severe Combined Immunodeficiency (SCID), the result of being bom with a broken gene that devastated their immune systems. The two young girls were the first to receive human gene therapy, a process where defective genes in the girls’ white blood cells were replaced with normal genes. Toufexis (1993) reveals the ethical dilemma that the National Institute of Health was confronted with after treating children who were short in height with a synthetic version of human growth hormone (HGH). The question was: “Should children who are healthy be given a drug made simply to change their looks?” (p. 49). Some readers of the article were appalled by the National Institute of Health’s experiment on healthy children, citing moral qualms with the issue (Letters, 1993d). Finally, Elmer-Dewitt (1993) discusses the possibility that technology may have gone too far when researchers successfully duplicated, or cloned, a human embryo. For the first time, manipulated cells came “not from plants or pigs or rabbits or cows, but from human beings.” (p. 65). The issue spawned both positive and negative reactions. While some felt technology had in fact gone too far in interfering with nature, others believed this was an accomplishment, not a setback in medical history (Letters, 1993f). One reason for this is the potential that exists in preventing and curing diseases. Robert Pirsig’s Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance (1974) and Theodore Kaczynski’s Manifesto (1995) were not created in a vacuum. There were real political, social, economic, and scientific events surrounding them. Technology received significant attention during both the 1970s and 1990s, and this attention focused on different ways that technology was influencing its respective time period. What must now be undertaken is a theoretical discussion of the method to be used in analyzing the ways Robert Pirsig and Theodore Kaczynski discuss technology with respect to society.
Some value terms take on special meaning. When people use them to represent multiple values they become ‘ideographs’. Thus, the word frontier, for example, becomes an ideograph. (Sillars, 1991, p. 129)Rokeach (1968) characterizes the term value as “an enduring belief that a specific mode of conduct or end-state of existence is personally or socially preferable to alternate modes of conduct or end-state of existence” (p. 160). Values should be distinguished from more specific statements, called beliefs. Whereas “life,” “liberty,” and “the pursuit of happiness” are values, “abortion is murder” is a belief (Sillars, 1994). Rokeach (1979) also notes that values can be organized in an effort to establish and reflect priorities. Where one sub-culture in American society might value individual freedom over collective welfare, another may value collective welfare over individual freedom. Values are not things we can point to directly in the material world. As McGee (1980) notes: “No one has ever seen an ‘equality’ strutting up the driveway, so if ‘equality’ exists at all, it has meaning through its specific applications” (p. 10). Values represent categories for thought and action that we create, usually in trying to inspire others toward higher goals or to steer them away from what we think they should not be thinking or doing. Not left unnoticed here is the fact that values are abstract, and by nature ambiguous and malleable within the societies in which they operate. Much like the concept of frontier, freedom is also a value. It is this particular concept that is a focus of my analysis. Both Pirsig and Kaczynski employ the concept of freedom throughout their discussion of technology and society, though they do this in different ways. Important here is that freedom is examined with respect to technology and society, as this is how Pirsig and Kaczynski generally treat it. Therefore, a broad discussion of freedom will be cast aside for a discussion of freedom more specifically geared toward technology and society. In other words, questions such as: How does living in modern (technological) society affect individual freedom? will be explored with respect to both authors. In order to effectively examine the ways each incorporates freedom into their work, I will utilize Michael Calvin McGee’s (1980) concept of the “ideograph.” McGee presented the ideograph to the field of Rhetorical Criticism in an attempt to create a link betweenrheforic and ideology. I define ideology loosely as the integrated assertions, theories, and [core] values of a given society. These elements operate to invoke what is right, wrong, and what ought to be within the given society. Early in his piece, McGee presents the following assertion:
Human beings in collectivity behave and think differently than human beings in isolation. The collectivity is said to have a “mind of its own” distinct from the individual...When one appears to “think” and “behave” collectively, therefore, one has been tricked...into accepting the brute existence of...“public mind” (p. 2)McGee proceeds into a discussion of the distinction between symbolists and materialists (specifically, “Marxians”). He argues that symbolists generally prefer to say that this “trick” is a sort of “transcendence,” a voluntary agreement to accept and engage a myth. Materialists, on the other hand, claim that the trick is essentially a lie, “a self-perpetuating system of beliefs and interpretations foisted on all members of the community by the ruling class” (p. 2). McGee states that, fundamentally, these two groups pursue two different studies:
The Marxian asks how the “givens” of a human environment impinge on the development of political consciousness; the symbolist asks how the human symbol-using, reality-creating potential impinges on material reality, ordering it normatively, “mythically.” (p. 3)While materialists neglect language studies and fail to adequately explain socially constructed realities, symbolists neglect the material environment and fail to adequately explain the impact of material phenomena on the construction of social reality. For McGee, ideology in general and the ideograph specifically is how gaps between the two groups can be bridged. The preceding discussion on symbolism and materialism functions to do two things: 1) ground McGee’s work, isolating some of his motivation for developing the concept of the ideograph, and 2) provide an initial, broadly-based definition of the ideograph, which can be characterized as a concentration of meaning that has material as well as symbolic implications. McGee suggests that ideology in practice is “a political language, preserved in rhetorical documents, with the capacity to dictate decision and control public belief and behavior” (p. 5). He continues in stating that the language which creates ideology is characterized by “slogans,” a vocabulary of ideographs. An analysis of these ideographs, McGee believes, reveals the many structures of public motives. I conceptualize the term “political” in its broadest sense. That is, while an ideograph may reveal the language structure behind an attempt to control public belief, and may be political in a broad sense, it may not necessarily be directly linked to politics as we normally associate the term. In other words, while “politics” always presupposes being “political,” the reverse is not the case as I argue it. The example offreedom as Pirsig discusses it serves to illustrate this. He attempts to shape human behavior and belief regarding technology, society, and freedom, but does so without specific mention to any political structure. Kaczynski does this as well, for the most part, though his argument does include references to “government” and “industrial society.” Ideographs are loaded words, existing in real discourse, functioning clearly and evidently as reflections of consciousness. It is also important to observe that, while it is not the focus of the present research, ideographs can be visual representations of a collective consciousness or focal points of an ideology (e.g., the peace symbol, the U.S. flag, etc.). Ideographs “are not invented by observers. They come to be as a part of the real lives of the people whose motives they articulate” (p. 7). They are language imperatives which McGee claims make “pure thought” perhaps impossible, as they are bound within the culture they help to define. Having discussed McGee’s concept of the ideograph, I will now turn to some of the ways ideographs have been examined in research. Ideographic analyses have been conducted on a wide range of issues and topics. Edwards and Winkler (1997) examine visual ideographs taking the form of print cartoons and the “Iwo Jima image.” Moore (1988) argues that the advantage of McGee’s approach is that “it allows the critic to identify specific language usages that reflect political commitments and orientations in real discourse” (p. 81). In a later piece (1997), Moore discusses the environmental debate over tobacco and smoking, and how the cigarette becomes, through its constant portrayal, a “representational ideograph.” Martin (1983) addresses the manner in which Jimmy Carter was able to construe an image of himself as “mirroring” the 19th century definition of “the best men” in light of Richard Nixon’s Watergate troubles. This definition was a compilation of an ideographic cluster which included “good moral character,” “competency,” and “intelligence.” Carter attempted to emulate such ideographs. He did so by opposing himself against Nixon, whom he claimed was, to borrow from Burke (1950), the “antithesis” of these terms. Lucaites and Condit (1990; 1993) are well-recognized for their work in charting the ways in which “equality” as an ideograph was invested with divergent content (integrationist or separatist). Lucaites and Condit give more weight to the potential for public influence over an ideograph’s meaning, and as such perhaps shed the ideograph in more of an “optimistic light” than McGee, who stresses the “potentially coercive dimensions of ideographic usage” (see Cloud’s 1998 discussion of Lucaites and Condit’s work on the ideograph “equality”). McGee, as mentioned, argues that it is possible ideographs may make “pure thought” impossible because of their very nature. The added spin Lucaites and Condit place on the ideograph is a helpful one, particularly for analyses such as my own, where the issue is not necessarily one involving a particular group (political or not) asserting power or influence over another, but rather individuals writing from their own perspectives in hopes of generating discussion and stimulating change. Readers of their work are not likely in a position of subservience, but are instead merely potential agents of change and action. Finally, Cloud (1998) examines the ideograph “family values” as it was deployed by republicans and democrats during the 1992 presidential election campaign. Dan Quayle’s speech on the alleged decline of family values in the midst of the urban riots in Los Angeles and through television series’ such as Murphy Brown is said to have been one of the instigators of this ideograph’s deployment. Cloud reveals that talk centering around family values served to scapegoat Black men and poor Americans for social problems (not to mention being disastrous for poor, Black men and women). That is, it was these particular groups of Americans that were not meeting their responsibilities as parents, according to this type of “talk.” Any combination of being Black, female, and poor served to magnify the blame that was placed on these individuals. While much of the research utilizing ideographic analysis as method has been centered around both the political in general and politics specifically, the present endeavor seeks to employ this method in a “non-political” arena, if you will. In this regard, it seeks to extend McGee’s discussion of the ideograph by examining the ways Robert Pirsig and Ted Kaczynski employ the value concept freedom without utilizing or incorporating specific political platforms (for the most part, as discussed). It also seeks to extend McGee’s work by analyzing one text that explicitly discusses freedom and one that does so at a more implicit and “definition-by-association” level. The Manifesto makes explicit, direct references to freedom (and autonomy). Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance, however, makes no such references. Instead, the 360-plus page book discusses terms such as peace-of-mind and control as related to technology and society. What I argue is that freedom is a concept that appears in the work of both Kaczynski and Pirsig. It does so, as mentioned, at different levels. I will primarily focus my attention inward at the texts, rather than outward at historical conceptualizations of freedom. This will be done for two reasons. First, I am examining freedom with respect to technology. This is an important point, for to examine the concept in its complete and broad sense would not only be an overwhelming task, but would overshoot my mark for the purposes of this research. Discussion of freedom with respect to technology and society has been far less prolific than an overall discussion of freedom (e.g., with respect to political systems of thought). Second, my primary purpose is to examine how Pirsig and Kaczynski discuss freedom, and looking directly at the ways each invokes the concept requires devoting much of my attention inward at the texts. Certainly, references and comparisons will be drawn against outside conceptualizations of freedom, but emphasis will be placed on the way each discusses the term, and the comparisons between the two. Because freedom is discussed at different levels by both authors, it is necessary to justify such an analysis. Cheney and Tompkins (1988) examine the many conceptualizations and levels of the concept text, and in comparing the empirical sciences highly efficient statistical means for analyzing text versus more literary or rhetorical ones, come up with a potential “rival” to empiricism. By utilizing Kenneth Burke’s (1964) theory of indexing, the critic can forge one “route toward validity and reliability in interpretation” (p. 464). Burke’s indexing method entails a series of propositions, one of which states that “the specific associations or relationships between terms of a text are of three general types: equations, implications, and transformations” (Cheney & Tompkins, 1988). Equations deal mostly with direct linkages or lines of opposition (the example provided is “War is evil”). Implications involve spin-offs of a term (e.g., how “order” might stem from “hierarchy” or “control”). Transformations reveal the “from what,” “through what,” and “to what” developments such as a syllogistic progression or a “yesterday-today- tomorrow” sequence (p. 466). It is at this level that inferences are more readily made and apparent. While both the Manifesto and Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance employ each of these associations with respect to freedom, the former more frequently utilizes equations and implications, whereas the latter adheres more to transformations, leaving the critic to draw inferences about how freedom enters into a particular minidiscussion within the text. Additionally, Cheney and Tompkins note Burke’s suggestion for the critic to “note operational synonyms of a word, terms that are synonymous to it in the text under consideration” (Cheney & Tompkins, p. 467). This is particularly relevant to an analysis of freedom in Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance, though it also comes into play with the Manifesto (e.g., the term “autonomy”). In the former, the term freedom is virtually absent from the entire text, and I will argue that operational synonyms for it do exist. Moreover, I argue that Pirsig’s rather tacit usage of the concept does not attenuate its significance in any way. McGee’s (1980) concept of the ideograph will be utilized in examining the value of freedom as it appears, either explicitly or implicitly, in the Manifesto and Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance. Building on Cloud’s (1998) and other prior research, I will denote the concept of freedom in carats (
Why is the body such an intense focus of attention in the academy today?....Is one reason so many of us are energetically studying the body precisely that we are undergoing fundamental changes in how our bodies are organized and experienced? (Martin, 1992, p. 543)In chapter one I discussed how Pirsig and Kaczynski assess the problem of technology and society in similar and different ways, and how they develop means for coping with this problem that are radically different from one another. I also discussed how the styles and structures of the two texts were quite different, with Pirsig’s being more poetic and multi-themed, and Kaczynski’s being more scientific and argumentative. Both authors also implicate the body differently in their discussions of technology and society. Pirsig implicates the body as a means for reconciling technology with society. That is, if one can engage both the physical and mental aspects of one’s own body, and strive for Quality in one’s work, hobbies....etc., then real progress can be made, according to Pirsig. Emphasizing both the physical and the mental makes sense when one considers that Pirsig seeks to adopt a “Zen-like” approach to reconciling technology with society. If the individual is to achieve a sense of oneness with their work, hobbies...etc., this is likely to be so because a similar sense is achieved at both the physical and mental levels of the individual body. Kaczynski on the other hand implicates the body primarily as an end, choosing to inform his reader of the ways the body will continue to be engaged in modern society as well as the way it ought to be engaged once a revolution against technology is carried out. For example, Kaczynski argues that technology strips the individual of proper physical engagement with the power process. Only through a more primitive lifestyle can one attain the type of fulfillment found in directly providing for one’s own vital needs, such as food, clothing and shelter. Additionally, Kaczynski strongly implicates the body by arguing that at the rate technological/modem-day society is “progressing,” individuals will become more and more isolated from their physical bodies by relying on ever-increasing [indirect] means for fulfilling vital needs. Additionally, he asserts that the time will come where we as individuals will progressively lose control of our own bodies, even at the very fundamental level of biological /genetic make-up. Thus, for Kaczynski, technology becomes part of and contributes to the artificial or inauthentic experience for human beings. Kaczynski instantiates this idea by citing developments in genetic engineering and [human] biological research. He argues that such developments are creating this trend. It becomes apparent through the work of Pirsig and Kaczynski that an analysis of the ways the body gets discussed in their work is both critical and central to an analysis of how these two authors reconcile technology with society. For both, the arguments that get developed center around the body, sometimes dealing explicitly with its implications and other times hovering around them, though seemingly never drifting more than an arm’s length from the focal point that is the body.[14] What is perhaps most appealing about examining these particular texts is the way in which the body is implicated in arriving at completely different means for coping with technology vis-a-vis society. As such, by conducting what I might call a “body-centered analysis,” a more thorough understanding of the ways technology gets discussed with respect to society (through Pirsig and Kaczynski, anyway) is attainable. Emily Martin (1992; 1994) suggests that in American society today the body is being experienced in dramatically different ways from the era of “Fordist mass production.” She characterizes the Fordist mass production system (perhaps most identified by the public through the image of the assembly line) as one which had as its goal efficiency, and utilized a production method geared to manufacturing large quantities of standardized products assembled with standardized components. Consequently, “Fordism” referred to the collective effort to create a new type of worker and a new type of man, one who could withstand the rigorous physical demands associated with this type of “mass-production” work. This particular worker would have to be in good health and good physical shape (1992). Currently, our bodies are suited more for what Martin terms an era of “flexible accumulation.” She states: “We are seeing not the end of the body, but rather the end of one kind of body and the beginning of another kind of body” (1992, p. 544). In other words, our bodies are not being utilized (and subsequently, experienced) as much for laborious purposes as they used to be, but are instead experiencing an intensification of the processes of deskilling and reskilling, particularly in the workplace. With this, the mental component of the body is drawing more and more weight than its counterpart, the physical. In this regard, individuals are being drawn further away from their physical selves, so-to-speak. Susan Faludi (1999) creates similar discussion in her recent work, but with special emphasis given to experiences held by males and the problems they encounter in trying to uphold socially constructed images of masculinity. For example, young men grow up with fathers who participated in the type of “Fordist” era Martin (1992) speaks of, or who participated in World War II. Today, men are too often deprived of the kinds of “opportunities,” if you will, to experience such masculinity. Because of societal, organizational, and technological development (these three overlap, obviously), men are left with conflicting notions of what it means to be masculine compared with the experiences of prior generations, Faludi argues. She claims that if males (and females) can get past these entrenched notions of what it means to be masculine, both sexes can begin to make progress toward a more liberating society at the level of gender.[15] Kaczynski, for example, probably would not cite the arguments laid out by Martin and Faludi as the primary motivation for his own theorizing, but would certainly have to acknowledge these issues as contributors to the problems that he argues technology poses for society.[16] While the body is central to both Pirsig’s and Kaczynski’s discussion of technology and society, it gets implicated in different ways. I will examine the ways both writers implicate the body in their respective works, and the style and structure of each text will prove to influence how the body is invoked. Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance is multi-themed and more poetic than the Manifesto, which is more argumentative and scientifically grounded. As such, Pirsig applies a greater use of metaphor in discussing the body when he moves from one theme of the book to another. For the most part, these metaphors exist in the more poetic, narrative theme of the author’s cross-country motorcycle trip with his son. They serve to emphasize the points he makes about technology and society in the intellectual framework he develops.[17] If one text were to more strongly invoke the notion of “the implicated body,” it would probably be the Manifesto. Kaczynski’s work is generally lacking in colorful metaphor and poetic style. Instead, his more argumentative and scientific approach results in a discussion of the body as it will likely be implicated in a society which continues along its present course of technological development. An additional result is a discussion of the way the body ought to be engaged and why Kaczynski believes a revolution against modem industrial society is necessary to arrive at this. In both cases, the body is central to Kaczynski’s primary argument. In the following brief chapter I will review what has been covered thus far and provide an overview of the remaining sections of the thesis.
People do not consciously and rationally choose the form of their society. Societies develop through processes of social evolution that are not under rational human control. (Kaczynski, p. 19)One of the central ways in which Kaczynski assesses technology is by appealing to the concept
Our lives depend on decisions made by other people; we have no control over these decisions and usually we do not even know the people who make them...our lives depend on whether safety standards at a nuclear power plant are properly maintained...The individual’s search for security is therefore frustrated, which leads to a sense of purposelessness, (p. 12)
Our current modes of rationality are not moving society forward into a better world. They are taking it further and further from that better world. (Pirsig, p. 102)Robert Pirsig’s employment of the concept
That’s the reason I’m checking it now. If it is a loose rod and I try to make it to the mountains without an overhaul, it will soon get louder and louder until the rod tears itself free, slams into the spinning crankshaft and destroys the engine, (p. 85).Pirsig is performing a check of the cycle in order to ascertain whether or not he can make it to the mountains. The reason he is able to make a judgment based on his observations is because he has taken the time to learn about the machine. The benefits of this are, again, peace of mind and a sense of control over the situation. The antitheses of these are feelings of helplessness and perhaps even paranoia. These would exist for an individual who has not taken the time to engage the motorcycle and understand its mechanics. It is assumed that for this individual, if the rod tears itself free and destroys the engine, what ensues will likely be feelings of anger and frustration, which are antithetical to
I’ve a set of instructions at home which...begin, “assembly of Japanese bicycle requires great peace of mind.”...Peace of mind...it’s the whole thing. That which produces it is good maintenance...The ultimate test’s always your own serenity. If you don’t have this when you start and maintain it while you’re working you’re likely to build your personal problems right into the machine... (p. 146)Here we have a direct reference to peace of mind, and Pirsig implicates it not only as an end state but as a necessary precursor to the Quality-seeking process. That is, not only will “good maintenance” produce it, but it must be present at the start of the maintenance process. I’ve discussed in detail the type of peace of mind that is an end, along with its relation to
Nonattainment [sic] of important goals results in death if the goals are physical necessities ... Consistent failure to attain goals throughout life results in defeatism, low self-esteem or depression ... Thus, in order to avoid serious psychological problems, a human being needs goals whose attainment requires effort, and he must have a reasonable rate of success in attaining his goals, (p. 7)The “physical necessities” are indicative of food, clothing, and shelter. Their attainment requires physical effort on the part of the individual, as long as the power process is engaged properly. This passage sets up later discussion of the argument that in modernday society, human beings do not have sufficient capabilities for engaging the power process in any significant way. Kaczynski asserts that human beings, instead of having these “real” goals, fall back on surrogate activities in hopes of finding fulfillment. In fact, the equating of physical necessities to “important goals” as it appears in the first sentence of the preceding passage suggests a preference for making one’s goals physical necessities. When this is not the case, psychological problems are implied to be a result.[40] Because most individuals are not required to exert themselves physically in order to procure necessities like food, clothing and shelter, Kaczynski argues that surrogate activites are what individuals pursue as a replacement. He suggests that surrogate activities are directed toward goals that people set up for themselves simply for the sake of having a goal to work toward (and the perceived fulfillment that results from this). Thus, if an individual takes up tennis, Kaczynski would reason this to be a surrogate activity because the individual would not pursue this activity if his/her effort were directed toward satisfying the vital needs of food, clothing and shelter. That is, as long as the effort directed toward satisfying vital needs requires the individual to use his or her physical and mental facilities in varied ways, then the desire to pursue surrogate activities such as tennis should remain absent.[41] Kaczynski observes that individuals assert a similar amount of effort in pursuing their surrogate activities that they would in pursuing real goals. A critic of Kaczynski might argue that if an individual is asserting physical effort toward a surrogate activity, and that surrogate activity provides fulfillment, then there is nothing wrong with having surrogate activities. Kaczynski would suggest that a problem does exist in that the power process (and consequently, the body) is not being engaged properly. Implied here is that surrogate activities do not adequately engage the power process because they come with strings attached. These strings amount to society and its constraints. Being able to pursue and engage surrogate activities means being on the “leash” that is society, and this translates into, according to Kaczynski, restricted levels of freedom. Here we see one example of just how closely related the concepts of freedom and the body are for Kaczynski. Essentially, the body cannot engage the power process properly in pursuing a surrogate activity because freedom is so restricted in other spheres of life.[42] The points discussed above receive additional attention in later passages:
In modem industrial society only minimal effort is necessary to satisfy one’s physical needs ... The only requirements are a moderate amount of intelligence, and most of all, simple OBEDIENCE. If one has those, society takes care of one from cradle to grave, (p. 8)
Many people who pursue surrogate activities will say that they get far more fulfillment from these activities than they do from ... satisfying their biological needs, but that is because in our society the effort needed to satisfy the biological needs has been reduced to triviality, (p. 8)In these passages, society is seen as “taking care of the individual” if the individual conforms to the system. As long as s/he chooses not to make physical necessities primary or “real” goals, the system will provide for him/her (speaking of the general population). Even further, it is implied that society, in providing for one’s vital needs, is not allowing the individual to adequately engage the body. Because society provides this, it is implied that only minimal effort is required to attain the goals of physical necessities. As a result, no real bodily effort is put forth by the individual in a significant way. This is articulated again in the second passage. It is suggested that people believe they get more fulfillment from pursuing surrogate activities than they do from satisfying biological needs. Here we can see similarites to previous discussion. Kaczynski suggests that individuals turn to surrogate activities for fulfillment “...because in our society the effort needed to satisfy biological needs has been reduced to triviality.” Thus, an individual works a job, gets paid, and provides for oneself, but does not do so by exerting oneself physically in a direct manner. That is, an individual may have to exert oneself physically at work, say as a construction worker, but this is done in order to secure a paycheck, which is then used to procure necessities such as food, clothing and shelter. No real physical effort is applied toward directly providing these vital necessities for oneself. Providing for one’s own physical necessities makes the process of providing much more significant, Kaczynski argues. He points out that it is in fact no surprise that society is full of surrogate activities, for individuals are searching for fulfillment. Society, in making it easy for individuals to secure physical necessities, has forced them to look elsewhere for it. If individuals were forced to exert themselves physically (and mentally) to procure these, there would be no need for surrogate activities. Kaczynski proceeds into a classification of what he calls “human drives,” of which he argues there are three types. The first type consists of drives that can be satisfied with very little effort, and in modem society vital needs like food and shelter unfortunately reside here (for many), acording to Kaczynski. The second type includes those drives which can be satisfied, but only through considerable effort on the part of the individual. The third type of human drives consists of those which cannot be satisfied regardless of the amount of effort put forth by the individual. These drives are relative to the individual. For example, certain individuals cannot become “supermodels” or “doctors” because their physical appearances or learning capabilities do not comply with society’s expectations for these occupations. Kaczynski asserts that the “power process” is intended to satisfy the drives of the second group (e.g., the pursuit of primary/real goals), but that modem society has pushed most human drives into either the first or third groups. The result of this, Kaczynski argues, is an increasing number of individuals who experience frustration, anger, depression...etc. What largely remains for the second type of human drives, those for which Kaczynski argues the power process is intended, are surrogate activities (e.g., jobs, hobbies). Kaczynski is imlpying here that individuals are not sufficiently satisfying those human drives which require serious effort. He reasons that surrogate activites have been inserted into this type of human drive, but that this is somehow not enough for the individual. Kaczynski suggests this to be the case in pointing to what he believes to be a significant and growing number of individuals who frequently experience feelings of frustration, anger...etc. Again there appears to be some equivocality in the way Kaczynski presents the argument, as the reader of the Manifesto is uncertain as to what sorts of things are being pursued in the first and third types of human drives. It can be assumed, though (and Kaczynski does attempt to clear this up in later passages), that for many individuals it is the physical necessities of food, clothing and shelter which are now a part of those drives which can be satisfied by exerting only a small amount of effort. Regarding those drives which cannot be satisfied even when effort is exerted, greater ambiguity exists. Perhaps Kaczynski would argue that autonomy is a central characteristic to drives in this group, and the perceived lack of this is what makes them impossible to achieve. For Kaczynski, the power process belongs in type two human drives, but this process must include a proper engagement of the body, and must therefore not include surrogate activities. It is here that Kaczynski makes reference to primitive societies, arguing that these societies satisfied physical necessities as a part of those drives requiring considerable effort, and the result was increased levels of fulfillment (and less frustration, anger...etc.). Much of Kaczynski’s discussion in what I have categorized as “improper engagement of the body” could arguably appear in the following section and vice-versa. However, it is my argument that dividing Kaczynski’s discussion of the body into categories allows for a clearer articulation of his reasoning. I now turn to what I consider to be a discussion of the ramifications of technology with respect to the body. **** Ramifications of technology Kaczynski asserts that technology is a primary contributor to the deprivation that occurs regarding the individual’s experience of the power process. One result includes feelings of frustration, unfulfillment, purposelessness...etc. Additionally, Kaczynski argues that the modem individual is obsessed with a notion of longevity and with maintaining physical vigor and attractiveness to an advanced age. Again, it is reasoned that this is a result of not significantly engaging the power process. It has been observed that Kaczynski advocates a more proper experience of the power process, one which engages the body both physically and mentally in pursuing vital necessities such as food, clothing and shelter. He argues that individuals instead apply the power process to surrogate activities in the search for fulfillment, and that feelings of frustration stem from being on the leash that is society. However, in the preceding passage Kaczynski is making a different sort of argument. This one holds that individuals are even more obsessed with their physical bodies than they would be if the power process were applied in an adequate manner. Because individuals in modem society have not engaged their bodies in pursuing real or primary goals, lack of fulfillment remains. The result of this is a greater amount of attention being devoted to maintaining one’s physical image. Indeed, Kaczynski explicates this point in the following passage:
Many modem people...are disturbed by the prospect of death...We argue that this is due to unfulfillment resulting from the fact that they have never put their physical powers to any use, have never gone through the power process using their bodies in a serious way. It is...the primitive man...whose need for the power process has been satisfied during his life who is best prepared to accept the end of that life. (p. 14)Kaczynski makes the perceived connection clearer between the modem individual’s fear of death (and growing old) and the type of unfulfillment that results from never experiencing the power process in a significant way. Essentially, it is argued that the obsession many individuals have with maintaining their bodies and physical appearance is a result of never engaging their bodies in the pursuit of real goals. Thus, not only are individuals unfulfilled, but they devote excessive amounts of attention to maintaining their bodies. Kaczynski proposes that this attention could be diverted elsewhere if the body was engaged properly, and the power process was directed toward satisfying one’s vital needs. In a later passage Kaczynski declares that even if the most cherished fruits of technology were preserved while the rest of the system were dismantled, these “fruits” would by themselves harbor evil. He uses the example of medicine, and argues that if cures for diseases such as diabetes were discovered, those individuals with a genetic tendency toward them would then be able to survive and reproduce as well as anyone. Kaczynski asserts that natural selection against such genes will cease and these genes will likely spread throughout the population. The image conjured here is that of an infected collective body that is the human race. It is argued that this may already be “in the works” today, in that advances in medicine and genetics are allowing many diseases to be controlled. This is a rare use of metaphor by Kaczynski, one which appears again later. Kaczynski suggests that there will inevitably be only one solution: a program designed to genetically engineer human beings. The result will be a human species that is, essentially, a manufactured product. This point will receive greater attention in the next section, where I examine Kaczynski’s discussion of the future with respect to the body. Kaczynski is accurate in arguing that many diseases will likely be cured, or at least sufficiently controlled. However, in asserting that there will inevitably be only one solution, the genetic engineering of human beings, Kaczynski leaves no room for the possibility that these diseases will be eliminated altogether. Furthermore, the argument can be made that if a cure is found for a disease that cannot be wiped out, then it really does not matter whether an individual’s genetic tendency toward that disease increases. Kaczynski might argue that these types of medical developments function to create an individual that will be much less “pure” than modem individuals. However, the appeal to what Kaczynski perceives to be an infected collective body leads him to a narrowly conceived vision of medical progress and the fate of the human race. Only one solution is envisioned, and no room is left for additional outcomes. The preceding mini-discussion provides a segue into Kaczynski’s discussion of what the future holds, and how the body is implicated. **** The future As discussed in the ideographic section, Kaczynski asserts that one of two scenarios will unfold where technology and society are concerned, and both have implications for the way we as a race will conceive of our bodies. In a continuation from a previous discussion on the potential for genetic engineering, Kaczynski connects this to what he refers to as government interference in the daily lives of its citizens:
If you think big government interferes in your life too much NOW, just wait till [sic] the government starts regulating the genetic constitution of your children. Such regulation will inevitably follow the introduction of genetic engineering of human beings, because the consequences of unregulated genetic engineering would be disastrous, (p. 23)Once again Kaczynski appeals to the metaphor of an infected collective body, and both technology and government regulation are sources of the “infection.” The implications for the body in a technological society are suggested to be so detrimental that we as a society will no longer have control over our own genetic make-up. The system will assert its dominance over us to such an extent that the future of the body will have to be conceptualized in an entirely different way. Words like “natural” and “biological” seemingly will be replaced by “artificial” and “genetically engineered.” The body, our bodies, will be altered to the system’s liking to the point where while we once conceived of our internal and biological states to be our own, now even this has surrendered to the system. The certainty invoked by Kaczynski is that technology is creating a physical and social environment for the human race that is radically different from the environment primitive man evolved through. Once again, the body and freedom are interwoven in this discussion. In making additional references to genetic engineering and the fate of the human race, Kaczynski argues that those aspects of the body that affect mental functioning will also be modified by the system. He proposes that the genetic engineering of human beings is actually taking its first shape in the form of gene therapy. Kaczynski reasons that it is only natural to assume such methods will make their way into the realm of mental functioning where humans are concerned. The implicit message suggests that the human race (and the body) will not only be affected at the physical level. Our mental capacities will also fall prey to the technological development of the system. Losing control over our own bodies at the physical as well as mental levels is not proposed to happen all at once.[43] Rather, Kaczynski argues it will take the form of a more gradual process. This process will be nearly impossible to resist, as each new “innovation” will appear by itself to be beneficial. Essentially, Kaczynski asserts that the human race will be forced to undergo a type of “social evolution.” That is, we will evolve to meet the demands of the social structure. The consequences of this evolution include a surrendering of how we presently conceptualize the control we have over our bodies. In a passage that received discussion in the ideographic section of the analysis, Kaczynski suggests that technology will eventually achieve near complete control over human behavior. He proceeds to reveal that it has been established that human behavior has a primarily biological basis. That is, researchers and experimenters have been able to demonstrate that sensations such as hunger, anger, and fear can be adjusted by electrically stimulating the brain. This passage creates more of a connection between biological functions of the body (including subsequent behaviors) and the potential for technology to tap into these in an effort to achieve control. If the reader of the Manifesto experiences feelings of skepticism about the potential for the genetic engineering of the human population, it can be argued that this passage serves to remove or at least alleviate some of that skepticism. To accomplish this, the argument proposed is one which makes the potential for technological control over human behavior (and physicality) that much more imminent. Kaczynski counters one future that envisions the human race without control over their bodies with another that envisions the human race living close to nature and engaging their bodies in a fulfilling manner. He argues that individuals, in the wake of an abolished technological structure, will be forced to live close to nature because this will be necessary for survival. In advocating what he calls “wild nature,” Kaczynski includes human nature. By this he means “those aspects of the functioning of the human individual that are not subject to regulation by organized society” (p. 36). Thus, while it may be difficult for individuals to adjust to a lifestyle absent of technology, the body will finally be engaging the power process in a way that it used to (e.g., primitive man) and a way that it ought to. In order to experience the power process through the body, individuals will procure vital necessities such as food, clothing and shelter by being peasants, herdsmen, fishermen, hunters...etc. Survival will be the primary goal as well as a constant motivation for the individual. Kaczynski argues that fulfillment will be the result of procuring vital necessities for oneself by engaging the body in a way that physical and mental effort are exerted in varied ways. Surrogate activities will cease to exist, and individuals will instead experience the power process by pursuing real or primary goals. Kaczynski argues it is here that the body will be engaged in ways that produce fulfillment. Moreover, by existing in a world removed from technology individuals will surrender recurrent feelings of frustration, purposelessness, and anger that Kaczynski argues to be so characteristic of living in modern society. My reader may recall Kaczynski’s assumption that not only are surrogate activities characteristic of improperly experiencing the power process (by not pursuing real goals), but that the perceived levels of fulfillment individuals get from these are actually counterbalanced by being on the “leash” that is modem society. Recall that consequences of being on this leash take the form of frustration, anger, and feelings of purposelessness, among other things. Therefore, Kaczynski suggests that even if individuals believe surrogate activities provide them fulfillment, this comes at a cost. Any fulfillment that may be experienced is essentially nullified. By living close to nature and free of technology, Kaczynski proposes that not only will the body be well served by experiencing the power process in the pursuit of real goals. In addition to this, individuals will discover fulfillment that comes with no strings attached. That is, feelings of frustration and anger that come with engaging the body by pursuing surrogate activities will no longer prevail. The benefits Kaczynski outlines take on multiple forms where the body is concerned. I have addressed the Manifesto’s discussion of what I call the implicated body. I argue that Kaczynski’s discussion of the body can best be understood by categorizing it into, namely: 1) improper engagement of the body, 2) ramifications of technology, and 3) the future. These categorizations are not necessarily mutually exclusive, as I have pointed out. Some of Kaczynski’s arguments could easily slide from one section to another. Despite this, I believe that by categorizing his overall argument with respect to the body in this way, a clearer articulation of that argument is allowed for. What can now be understood from the Manifesto is that: o An improper engagement of the body leads to an improper engagment of the power process, and in modem society individuals rely upon surrogate activites for what is perceived to be fulfillment, rather than relying upon primary or real goals. o Relying upon surrogate activities leads individuals to, ironically, continued feelings of unfulfillment due to the consequences that accompany being on the leash that is modem society (e.g., the obsession with maintaining one’s physical appearance that is a result of never engaging the body in a significant manner). o The future poses two possibilities for the human race. One is depicted essentially as an infected collective body, where advances in medicine and genetic engineering allow for near complete control over behavior to occur. The other is depicted as a race living close to nature, engaging the body physically and mentally in the pursuit of primary goals. One result of this is increased levels of fulfillment and freedom. It has become evident that the line separating freedom and the body in the Manifesto’s discussion of technology is a fairly blurred one. A significant portion of the arguments presented about the body also incorporate concepts like control and autonomy. Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance creates a distinction between freedom and the body that is a bit less blurry, and it is here that I now turn. *** Pirsig and The Implicated Body Pirsig relies on more than one theme in presenting arguments about technology and its implications for the body. For example, the theme of the cross-country motorcycle trip, which I would call the “story” theme, functions to inform Pirsig’s discussion of Quality by presenting the reader with various metaphors and analogies. This second theme, the intellectual framework Pirsig develops regarding the nature of Quality, is enriched by the way the first theme is structured, and vice-versa. The following analysis will probe Pirsig’s use of one theme to inform another, and how the body is implicated in both.[44] I will then proceed into a discussion of Pirsig’s reflections about the nature of Quality, where the body is concerned. Finally, I will devote a specific section to Pirsig’s discussion of gumption, as this has significant implications for the body. **** Themes, metaphor, and analogy The language used in Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance reveals interesting connections between the “body” and the main focus of Pirsig’s work...the intellectual framework he sets forth. Specifically, Pirsig utilizes metaphor and/or analogy to invoke the body in one theme of the book — that of the cross-country motorcycle trip with his son. The use of metaphor and analogy is done so in such a way as to implicate the body in his more theoretical discussion of how technology can be reconciled with modem society. An interesting observation is that while Pirsig argues that one must engage the body in one’s pursuit of Quality, he also makes use of several body references and physical terms in connecting the story theme to this discussion of Quality. Examples of this will be illustrated through some of the upcoming passages. During the story theme of the text Pirsig observes that things are seen on a motorcycle in a way that is completely different from being in a car. In a car the individual has a sense of being enclosed, and this sense contributes to a feeling that one is a passive observer in which scenes occur and disappear almost in a kind of frame. The cyclist experiences no such frame, Pirsig argues, and the feeling of being completely in contact with it all is ever-present. Pirsig notes: You’re in the scene, not just watching it anymore, and the sense of presence is overwhelming” (p. 4). This passage appears early in the text, and one may wonder how this is at all connected with the body and/or Quality. Pirsig is advocating very early that a distinction exists between those individuals who discover and engage Quality and those who do not. The individual behind the wheel of a car is not engaging the scene, while the cyclist is. This sets up later discussion in the text which proposes that to pursue Quality, one must engage an object, craft, job...etc. in similar fashion. The individual who is on the path toward Quality will feel like s/he is experiencing an object or craft, and that this experience is never removed from immediate consciousness. The body comes into play only implicitly here, for to pursue Quality, Pirsig argues that the body must be engaged both physically and mentally.[45] In another early passage, Pirsig mentions that he and his son are traveling across the country with some friends, and that secondary roads are preferred over main highways and freeways. Pirsig adds that while they strive to make good time, the emphasis ought to be placed on the term good rather than time. He argues that when this shift in emphasis is made, one’s entire approach changes. For example, while twisting hilly roads are long in terms of time, they are also much more enjoyable on the cycle than stretches of flat, barren land. Pirsig is offering illustrations about the process of riding the cycle and vacationing, but more is going on here. The argument is made that when riding, an emphasis ought to be placed on the good in making good time. While certain stretches of land may seem more time consuming, they are worth it if they are enjoyable. The same will be argued about dealing with technology and pursuing Quality in the other theme to Pirsig’s text, the intellectual framework he develops. The implication is that the pursuit of Quality might be a lengthy one, such as with maintaining one’s motorcycle, but it is also much more enriching and enjoyable if one has an understanding for Quality. Part of what makes motorcycle maintenance a lengthy process is the amount of detail involved in caring for the cycle and the patience one must have in doing so. Again, the body is only implicitly present in this discussion, as the connection between the pursuit of Quality and proper engagement of the body is a necessary one to recall. This will receive more detailed attention shortly. Pirsig mentions that one character,. “Sylvia,” was almost flown out to Montana instead of cycling out with the rest of the characters in the story. Pirsig asserts that this would have been a mistake, for arriving in the Rocky Mountains by plane would be to see them in an entirely different way than after days of hard travel on the motorcycle. It is argued that the airplane traveler would view the Rockies as “pretty scenery,” while the cyclist looks upon them as “a goal, a promised land” (p. 18). Though Pirsig doesn’t explicitly mention it, the assumption is given that the airplane traveler would not possess the appreciation for the Rocky Mountains that the cyclist would. Once again, an analogy is being drawn between riding the motorcycle across country (story theme) and the pursuit of Quality (reflective theme, intellectual framework). Pirsig implies that individuals who pursue Quality in their activities have to work harder and put in more time, but end up possessing a greater appreciation for the nature of that activity, object, job...etc. This will likely be at least in part a result of the type of relationship the individual forges with his or her “pursuit.” Recall prior discussion that the individual that eliminates subject-object dualisms and considers himself or herself to be in a sort of relationship with that “pursuit” will feel as though an investment has been made in it, and this allows for a greater feeling of appreciation for it. While the preceding passages have served to illustrate the connection Pirsig makes between multiple themes in the text, the body has only implicitly been linked to them — as a significant component of Quality. However, the following passages serve to illustrate not only this continued implicit notion of the body vis-a-vis Quality, but also an employment of the body in physical motion as a means to connect the story theme to Pirsig’s reflective theme. Essentially, the body appears at both ends of the connection Pirsig attempts to create between the two themes. Invoking the body in the story theme of the text allows Pirsig to create emphasis on the body in his more reflective discussion about the needfor individuals to pursue Quality. One metaphor and subsequent analogy that Pirsig draws upon is that of the mountain. It is here that one can begin to see more of an employment of the body concept at both ends of the connection Pirsig is attempting to make. One of the best indicators that the metaphor of the mountain serves to implicate both the body and the pursuit of Quality in a technological society is the following passage:
Mountains like these and travelers in the mountains and the events that happen here are found not only in Zen literature but in the tales of every major religion. The allegory of a physical mountain for a spiritual one that stands between each soul and its goal is an easy and natural one to make. Like those in the valley behind us, most people stand in sight of the spiritual mountains all their lives and never enter them. (p. 167)The final sentence of this passage suggests that in general most people stay at the “valley” level; that is, they don’t make intellectual or spiritual pursuits of any real significance. Specifically, it is implied that most people don’t take the time to pursue Quality in their everyday lives. As I’ve discussed, striving for Quality means eliminating subject-object dualisms, and this requires more effort on the part of the individual. Using the example of motorcycle maintenance, it requires taking the time to learn about the machine (something most people are not willing to do). Additionally, it requires being methodical and patient in one’s upkeep of the cycle. The “working relationship” between individual and cycle must be established. While traversing a mountain “physically” gets related to the kind of effort most people put into their endeavors, it is the “spiritual” mountain most need to confront if Quality is to be achieved. In the midst of climbing the mountain, Pirsig informs that reader that a short rest is needed, and this is due to the weight of the backpacks. He adds: “There’s a negative reaction to all the weight. As we go on though, it’ll become more natural” (p. 174). The climber of the mountain is having to adjust to the weight of the pack much in the same way individuals who first discover and seek to pursue Quality have to adjust becoming more observant, patient, diligent, and skilled. By declaring that the weight of the pack will become more natural, it can be implied that individuals will eventually accustom themselves to the Quality process. For example, an individual like the character “John,” who regards technology from a romantic perspective and does not care to explore the underlying form of his cycle, would feel awkward at first if he began to maintain his own cycle and look at it from a classic perspective. However, eventually he would come to appreciate this process and treat it as “natural.” The mountain metaphor appears again a few pages later:
You climb the mountain in an equilibrium between restlessness and exhaustion. Then, when you’re no longer thinking ahead, each footstep isn’t just a means to an end but a unique event in itself. This leaf has jagged edges. This rock looks loose ... To live only for some future goal is shallow. It’s the sides of the mountain which sustain life, not the top. Here’s where things grow. (p. 183)The act of climbing a mountain and the process involved (pushing the body, asserting effort) is described, but there is more going on here. Pirsig suggests that when you no longer only have your eye on the “ends,” but instead start to indulge in the “means” or process, you escape the realm of shallowness and work toward what I would call fulfillment. The “equilibrium” mentioned here can be translated over to the everyday world of the individual, wherein s/he achieves a sort of harmony with what s/he is doing. This is analogous to one’s job, hobbies, or in Pirsig’s case again, motorcycle maintenance. Becoming familiar with the process of motorcycle maintenance, and not just with how it rides or handles, is a “unique event in itself.” It allows one to appreciate the “sides of the mountain.” With respect to technology, this is viewed as liberating for the individual. No longer would one be at the mercy of how the machine chooses to function. Rather, should an individual choose to explore the underlying form of the cycle, s/he would be able to understand it better, and have more control over how s/he wants it to perform. Conceivably, technology’s grip on the individual would begin to loosen. The aforementioned passage provides the reader a glimpse into how such an “equilibrium” gets applied. The final sentence of the passage, “Here’s where things grow,” has an organic appeal to it, and this gets related to the body in a later passage in which Pirsig is no longer within the “story,” but is now adding to his intellectual framework (the two seesaw back and forth throughout the text):
In pursuit of this ghost he (Phaedrus) went on to wider meanings of Quality which drew him further and further to his end...I’ve no intention of going on to that end...He just passed through this territory...! intend to stay and cultivate it and see if I can get something to grow ... A real understanding of Quality doesn’t just serve the System, or even beat it or even escape it. A real understanding of Quality captures the System, tames it, and puts it to work for one’s own use... (p. 200)Terms like cultivate and captures pose images of the body in action. To cultivate an area of discussion and to see if one can “...get something to grow” present agricultural metaphors regarding a physical body at work on a farm or in a garden. Pirsig is explaining that he wants to explore the realm of Quality with respect to everyday living — most specifically, living in a technological world. In doing so, he presents powerful imagery of the body at work. Additionally, the term captures in almost any context allows for the image of a set of hands reaching out to grab something, then clutching it to a point where it cannot escape. Pirsig, in trying to discuss how Quality can lead to liberation within a technological society, presents powerful imagery not of the body as static, but as dynamic in carrying out an action. One final passage within the Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance reveals in powerful fashion the manner in which the mountain serves as a metaphor for the pursuit of Quality, and with respect to the body:
We come to a rough grade and it changes to two breaths per step. At one bank it goes to four breaths per step. Huge steps, almost vertical ... The aspen staves come in handy now ... the packs make you top-heavy and the sticks are good insurance against toppling over. You plant one foot, plant the staff, then SWING on it, up, and take three breaths, then plant the next foot, plant the staff and SWING up... (p. 199)The speaker is engaged in a steep, physical climb up the mountain. It is somewhat exhausting, and he is forced to take longer breaths. By the end of the passage, he is describing the methodical nature of the climb. “You plant one foot, plant the staff, then SWING on it, up, and take three breaths, then plant the next foot...” The fact that three breaths are needed between each step suggests how methodical and patient the climber needs to be in this situation. This is analogous to Pirsig’s explication of the pursuit of Quality in the everyday world. In fact, the passage is a prime example of the pursuit itself. The individual needs to be methodical and patient when engaging anything if s/he wants to be doing it properly. Things might seem slow and time-consuming, but Pirsig would argue that there is nothing wrong with this. In fact, this is what getting at the process of things entails. Essentially, this is necessary for the achievement of both liberation and fulfillment in modern-day society. This is presented as the method for coping. The preceding passage serves as a sort of mini-illustration to the reader for how to apply it. Pirsig relies on one theme, that of the cross-country motorcycle trip story, to shed light on the more theoretical theme that is his reflections about the nature of Quality. He does so in different ways, though. In some instances the body is only subtly implied, as it can never be far removed from what it means to pursue Quality. Thus, it is here that Pirsig implicates it at only one end of the link he attempts to make between themes. Other instances exist where Pirsig implicates it at both ends of the connection drawn. In an effort to explicate the former instances better, I will turn to a discussion of what I’ve made generalizations about throughout this thesis thus far: Pirsig’s more theoretical comments about the significance of the body to the Quality process. This will include a later discussion of the body and gumption, which is a key component to Pirsig’s development of the concept Quality. **** Reflections invoking the body Pirsig argues that engaging the body in the pursuit of Quality entails not only physical engagement, but mental engagement as well. One example he offers is the case of the auto or cycle mechanic. Pirsig asserts that untrained observers often perceive the mechanic’s work largely to be made up of physical labor. However, this is only a small part of the mechanic’s job. The physical labor exerted by the mechanic actually works in concert with the type of careful observation and precise thinking that constitute mental engagement. This of course carries with it the assumption that the mechanic adopts a craftsmanlike approach to work. Pirsig suggests that if one were to observe the expression of a novice workman and compare it to that of a craftsman whose work is known to be excellent, the difference would be visible. For example, the craftsman never proceeds in a straight line. Rather, decisions are made as the work unfolds. For this reason, Pirsig suggests that the craftsman will be absorbed and attentive to what s/he is doing without deliberately contriving this. Essentially, the motions of the craftsman will be in a kind of harmony with, in this case, the machine. The larger point Pirsig attempts to drive home here is that the divorce of art from technology is unnatural. That is, individuals now see technology as being distant and removed from the artistic process. Pirsig would advocate that technology, and the engagement of technology, is as much an artistic process as painting and songwriting. Pirsig ponders at one point how strange it is that old, obsolete buildings and the technology of fifty and a hundred years ago always appears to look better than its modem successors. Implied here is that what prevailed in the past was a more craftsmanlike approach to engaging technology. This approach had as its end Quality. Thus, a construction worker who was assigned to help construct a building engaged his or her body in such a way as to pursue Quality. The result would be a building, plant, or mill that stands the test of time because it is done right. Pirsig communicates this feeling when he contemplates this older technology and compares it with newer forms of technology that do not seem to exude such craftsmanship.[46] Pirsig utilizes another metaphor, that of the stream, in arguing that individuals are searching for additional fulfillment in the wake of having vital necessities such as food, clothing and shelter provided for (thanks in part to technology):
Now the stream of our common consciousness seems to be obliterating its own banks, losing its central direction and purpose...and to no particular purpose other than the wasteful fulfillment of its own internal momentum. Some channel deepening seems called for. (p. 7)The stream is connected to the collective mindset of modem society, and it is argued that individuals are caught up in a world of unfulfillment even though something more is desired. Whereas for many the vital needs of food, clothing and shelter are no longer a challenge to procure, what remains are feelings of emptiness and futility that individuals appear to be experiencing. Pirsig asserts that the result of this is a lack of recognition where Quality is concerned. The “channel deepening” that seems necessary is implied to be a new approach to engaging technology. This approach has as its centerpiece the concept of Quality, and individuals must exert themselves physically and mentally in pursuing it if they are to attain sufficient levels of fulfillment. An incident Pirsig encounters while on the road serves to illustrate the argument that art and technology should not be separated. Pirsig has to stop into a small welder’s shop to have a chain guard fixed for his cycle. He explains the problem to the welder, an older gentleman, and the welder proceeds to fix the chain guard in a more intricate and delicate manner than Pirsig admits he ever could. Pirsig is forced to ask himself: “Who appreciates work like this anymore?” (p. 321). The way in which the scene is set up and played out suggests that the welder is perceived by Pirsig to be a craftsman, one who engages his work in such as a way as to pursue Quality. The end result is a job done right, even better than Pirsig confesses he could do. In the following section, I will examine a key concept to Pirsig’s reflections about Quality: gumption. **** Gumption and the body Pirsig characterizes gumption as being what happens to the individual who connects with Quality. This connection does not necessarily mean Quality is already achieved. It could simply mean that an understanding of Quality has been acquired. Pirsig observes that individuals who return from a peaceful vacation, say a long fishing trip, seem to be filled with gumption. He argues that when he repairs his motorcycle, an adequate supply of gumption is necessary at the start, for it is the “psychic gasoline” that keeps the him going. Pirsig suggests that just as easily as the physical and mental capacities of an individual can be working together because of gumption, a lack of it can lead to frustration, anger, and impatience. Gumption is an essential component to the Quality process, and its presence or absence will be visible in the type of physical and mental effort exuded by the individual. Pirsig illustrates:
Throughout the process of fixing the machine things always come up, low- quality things, from a dusted knuckle to an accidentally ruined “irreplaceable” assembly. These drain off gumption, destroy enthusiasm and leave you so discouraged you want to forget the whole business. I call these things “gumption traps.” (p. 274)Pirsig asserts that gumption traps, if they do not leave the individual wanting to drop the entire Quality pursuit, will lead to improper bodily engagement for the individual. That is, the individual will engage his or her body physically and mentally in such a way that anything but Quality will be the outcome. This point receives further development later, as gumption traps are isolated into two main types: setbacks and hang-ups. During setbacks, the individual is proposed to be thrown off the path to Quality by external conditions. Utilizing Pirsig’s example of motorcycle maintenance, the individual might encounter parts trouble, wherein a certain part might be needed that is not already present. Thus, the individual has to search the city for a mechanic or parts store that carries the part in question. This can lead to frustration, and the implied message is that when the individual returns to his cycle to repair it, the potential exists for a lower Quality experience regarding that pursuit.[47] The body is implicated at the level of improper physical and mental engagement in repairing the cycle. The second type of gumption trap — hang-ups — poses even greater implications for the body. This type of trap is more a result of the internal conditions of the individual, and Pirsig classifies these into three types: 1) value traps, such as ego, anxiety, boredom and impatience; 2) truth traps, where the individual assumes for example that “yes’ or “no” is the answer to a question, rather than acknowledging the possibility of “maybe” or even “there is no answer at this time”; and 3) muscle traps, such as working in bad surroundings, using bad tools, or what Pirsig calls “muscular insensitivity.” The first and third types of hang-ups have the greatest implications for the body. For example, value traps like an over-sized ego and feelings of anxiety, boredom and/or patience will in all likelihood result in an improper mental engagement of the body. This translates into poor physical performance, and the end result is a low-Quality experience for the individual. If an individual’s ego gets in the way of accepting new forms of thought where the cycle is concerned, this blockage will function as a deterrent to Quality. Similarly, feelings of boredom, anxiety, impatience and even fatigue create blockage, and it will be more difficult for the individual to experience Quality. In the story theme of the text, Pirsig illustrates how fatigue and impatience contribute to a low-Quality experience. Exhausted after a long day of traveling, the four characters (Pirsig, Chris, John and Sylvia) try to set up camp and prepare food. Their bodies are physically tired, and perceiving only one-half hour of remaining daylight leads to feelings of impatience where setting up camp is concerned. They try to rush through the process, but are too tired to do anything effectively. In the end they are just glad to get to sleep.[48] Regarding muscle traps, if an individual buys ineffective or poorly constructed tools and turns up the volume of the radio while trying to repair a cycle, the end result will once again be a lower Quality experience than what could be achieved.[49] Both concentration and performance will be what suffers. For this reason, it is imperative that an individual be comfortable with one’s tools, one’s knowledge of those tools, and one’s surroundings. Pirsig also asserts that muscular insensitivity can be a gumption trap. This can best be characterized as a lack of ability to perform very precise tasks at the level of physical engagement. For example, in maintaining the cycle, Pirsig speaks of certain tools which he refers to as precision instruments. These tools are meant to be applied to extremely intricate components of the cycle (often very expensive components, as well). If an individual has “shaky hands,” s/he will probably be forced to recognize the gumption trap Pirsig refers to as muscular insensitivity.[50] Where muscular insensitivity largely entails a physical engagement of the body, the notion of stuckness appears to deal more with mental engagement. It is certain though, with stuckness and other gumption-related concepts, that proper or improper mental engagement of the body will directly motivate proper or improper physical engagement. Pirsig suggests:
Stuckness shouldn’t be avoided. It’s the psychic predecessor of all real understanding. An egoless acceptance of stuckness is a key to an understanding of all Quality, in mechanical work as in other endeavors, (p. 257)Pirsig places a positive spin on the idea of being stuck in one’s pursuit. An implicit suggestion is that if one possesses gumption, stuckness will not prevail for long. The individual, provided s/he avoids the gumption trap of an over-sized ego, will eventually slip out of this state of stuckness and back on the path to Quality. Pirsig explicates this discussion by detailing Chris’ trouble with writing a letter to his mother. Chris does not know where to begin, and Pirsig informs him that getting stuck is common. It usually occurs when one is trying to think of (or do) too many things at once. Rather than trying to figure out what to say and what to say first, Pirsig advises Chris to sort out all of the things he wants to say to his mother in the letter. This is analogous to Pirsig’s discussion of the motorcycle. For example, in assembling or taking apart the cycle, Pirsig recommends keeping specific track of the order things are done. This type of organization will ensure that the individual accomplishes everything s/he wants, and that each thing gets accomplished in a specific order. Doing this not only ensures that one will sustain present levels of gumption, but that specific gumption traps will also be avoided. Pirsig argues that individuals who possess gumption reveal a type of inner quietness and peace of mind. This peace of mind paves the way to Quality, part of acquiring it means recognizing the various levels at which it occurs. For example, physical quietness is a necessary component to peace of mind. This entails working at a level of quietness that promotes concentration and attentiveness to one’s endeavor, and Pirsig argues this to be the easiest to achieve. Mental quietness occurs when one has no wondering thoughts at all. Related to this is value quietness, where one performs the acts of his pursuit without any wondering desires at all. Pirsig argues this type of quietness to be the most difficult to achieve. The implication is that if one is able to mentally engage the body in this fashion, then the type of physical application that results from this will almost certainly lead one to Quality. I have addressed the implicated body in Pirsig’s discussion of technology. Pirsig asserts that technology can be reconciled with modem society as long as individuals reassess their own values in a way that both recognizes and pursues Quality. The body is the “vehicle” through which such effort is exerted. Physical and mental engagement are necessary to arrive at Quality. In summarizing: o Pirsig uses the story theme in Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance to inform the more reflective theme about the nature of Quality. In doing so, the body is implicated at the more subtle level of its connection to Quality. o Additionally, there are instances in which Pirsig invokes the body in a physical way by presenting it in the story theme, but also connecting it to his more theoretical discussion about Quality. At times, the image conjured is that of a body in motion, either climbing a mountain or at work in a garden. o Pirsig reflects on technology and its implications for the body, and one of the more focal ways this is done appears in his discussion of gumption. Gumption entails both physical and mental engagment of the body, and avoiding gumption “traps”can lead to Quality. I will now compare and contrast the ways Pirsig and Kaczynski implicate the body in their overall discussions. *** Kaczynski, Pirsig, and The Implicated Body One can recall Kaczynski’s argument that individuals must first break free from technology and modem society before an adequate engagement of the body can occur. Once this type of freedom is procured individuals will be able to engage the body as Kaczynski argues it ought to be engaged. That is, individuals will exert their bodies both physically and mentally in pursuing real goals (as opposed to surrogate activities). Essentially, the need for the power process will be served, according to Kaczynski. Because individuals will be free from technology, the body will be engaged properly and, subsequently, increased levels of freedom and fulfillment will prevail. Kaczynski invokes the body as an end, where a necessary precursor to its proper engagement is the abolition of the modern technological system. This differs from the ways Pirsig implicates the body. Pirsig suggests that what is first needed in the quest for freedom and fulfillment is a proper physical and mental engagement of the body. This can be achieved alongside technology and within modem society, as long as individuals re-assess their values to include an understanding and pursuit of Quality. If this is done, individuals will no longer feel frustrated by and alienated from technology. Rather, the opposite will prevail. Pirsig argues that the body is the means by which individuals can procure sufficient levels of freedom, fulfillment and purpose. This can only be accomplished, though, if individuals discover Quality and pursue it in their jobs, hobbies, and everyday tasks. Once Quality is recognized, the individual will use his or her body to physically and mentally pursue it in the aforementioned endeavors. Thus, where Kaczynski connects the body to the power process, Pirsig connects it to Quality. Pirsig and Kaczynski implicate the body at different levels of their overall argument, but discussing the body differently can also be attributed to the stylistic differences that exist between the Manifesto and Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance. Kaczynski‘s argumentative and rationalistic approach to the Manifesto leaves him discussing the body merely as it should he engaged (and how this is not the case in modem society). That is, individuals have a need for the power process, but that need can only be served if the individual breaks free from modem industrial-technological society. Part of the reason Kaczynski discusses the body predominantly in this manner only is that he presents an argument that is not multi-themed. Pirsig, however, incorporates multiple themes in Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance. The body receives attention not only in his theoretical and reflective theme, but in the story theme as well. The reader of the text is presented with multi-leveled images of the body. One potential result of this is a perception that the body is more significant to Pirsig’s argument than it is to Kaczynski’s. I argue that this conclusion would be misleading, for in referring back to the diagram of both authors’ overall argument, it becomes evident that the body is treated as one step in the “recommendations” of both Pirsig and Kaczynski. It is just that for Pirsig the body crosses over from one theme into another.
It is the promise of technology that has both fueled and disguised the gigantic transformative endeavors that have given our time its character. (Borgmann, p. 35)Both Pirsig and Kaczynski accurately detect that problems exist with how individuals cope with technology and modem society. Both authors suggest that levels of freedom and fulfillment are perceived to suffer, either at the hands of the entire technological system (in Kaczynski’s case) or from the way individuals engage technology (in Pirsig’s case). Pirsig and Kaczynski are correct in arguing that freedom and the body are core concepts in addressing technology’s impact on the individual. Both authors do good work illuminating these concepts, despite the fact that freedom and the body appear in different areas and in different ways in their overall arguments.[53] However, in proposing ways for how we as a society ought to respond to issues such as freedom and fulfillment where technology is implicated, both authors fall short in their analyses. Borgmann’s (1984) discussion of technology serves to illuminate the shortcomings of both Kaczynski and Pirsig. Kaczynski suggests that the body cannot be engaged properly in modem society. This is so because the power process cannot be experienced in a significant way. Individuals must revolt against and break free from the current technological structure, which Kaczynski argues to be the source of restricted levels of freedom, increased feelings of frustration and purposelessness, and surrogate activities. In many ways Kaczynski articulates ideas proposed by Ellul (1964) and Marcuse (1968 ). Recall that these philosophers both assert that freedom is frequently restricted in modem technological society (e.g., by providing us with “more” to be accountable to, such as increasing means of communication). Additionally, superficial needs are foregrounded as a result of having vital needs provided for without the exertion of serious effort. For example, individuals who do not directly provide for their own vital needs more often than not take up hobbies or direct their efforts toward the acquisition of material goods. Kaczynski would suggest that these superficial needs are pursued through surrogate activities. The end result of this is a body that is not engaged properly, as well as continued restrictions placed on individual freedom. Borgmann responds to this issue by arguing that the body can be engaged properly and individuals can experience sufficient levels of freedom and fulfillment in modem society. What is advocated is not a revolution against technology per se, but a shift in the way technology is perceived and embraced. Borgmann proposes that individuals ought to place the phenomenon of technology in the background of their daily lives rather than foregrounding it. That is, rather than relying on technology to such a point that it contributes to defining oneself, the individual ought to place it in such a role that it merely complements one’s life. Borgmann develops the concept of the device paradigm in explicating the ways individuals can fall into the trap of foregrounding technology and experiencing perceived feelings of unfulfillment. One example given is that of the central heating plant. While heat used to be something individuals had to exert serious effort to procure, today it is acquired for many by simply adjusting a thermostat. One result of this is that individuals no longer have to exert serious effort in order to secure this necessary need. Thus, the physical effort that used to be applied toward producing heat, often through a woodstove, is either channeled elsewhere or left in a static state. The device paradigm makes genuine engagement virtually impossible. This leads to another result of the device paradigm — that individuals feel removed from that which provides for them. A heating plant can be perceived as an ominous, obscure entity, one which is responsible for the production of a crucial product. The experience of having such a need provided by a largely mysterious entity can be an unsettling one for the individual. This speaks to Kaczynski’s claim that individuals feel their lives are in the hands of mysterious forces or people, and that it is necessary to remove oneself from technology in order to arrive at genuine freedom and fulfillment. Borgmann suggests that the focal practice is the answer in sustaining levels of freedom and fulfillment, while at the same time engaging the body properly. Focal practices allow the individual to place the phenomenon of technology in the background of daily life. When this is accomplished, things like central heating plants take on a more positive meaning in the lives of individuals. They are seen for what they are — innovations that improve the quality of everyday life. In articulating the nature of the focal practice, Borgmann asserts:
A focal practice, generally, is the resolute and regular dedication to a focal thing. It sponsors discipline and skill which are exercised in a unity of achievement and enjoyment, of mind and body. (p. 219)One example of a focal practice given by Borgmann is running. For the runner, the road is a focal thing. The runner makes demands on one’s skill in engaging the road. Skiing is also a focal practice, and it is the slope that is a focal thing for the skier. One might suggest that in fact technology is still foregrounded for these individuals, as they rely on technology in order to engage these focal practices and things. Borgmann responds that technological engagement is certainly present, as these activities depend on running shoes, skis, ski boots, etc. However, these technological devices do not procure but mediate focal engagement. The individual still must exert effort and apply skill toward these practices, and engagement in the end comes with the road, the slope, etc.[54] For Borgmann, focal things and practices can empower society to propose and potentially enact a reform of technology, by first placing it in the background of daily life, and then opening up public discussion of it as a phenomenon. This latter point will receive greater attention later. Kaczynski would suggest that discussion about reform within technology and. finding fulfillment and freedom alongside technology neglects the imminent threat it poses to human freedom. Recall previous arguments in the Manifesto which state that technology will eventually acquire near complete control over human behavior, and that the genetic engineering of our species will become an ever-present reality in the future. Thus, not only would freedom suffer, but our bodies would also succumb to the pressures of technology. Borgmann proposes:
What is needed if we are to make the world truly and finally ours again is the recovery of a center and a standpoint from which one can tell what matters in the world and what merely clutters it up. A focal concern is that center of orientation, (p. 225).Not getting caught up in all of the “clutter” is the challenge for individuals. A focal concern is one which recognizes focal things and practices, and if individuals can recognize these, it is argued that much of the clutter will inevitably fade to the background of daily life. For example, the world of commodities and consumption is a growing one, but if individuals adopt more of a focal concern, less attention will be given to a pursuit of commodities and a consumption of consumer goods. Focal things and practices take up time through their engagement. A focal concern does more than illuminate focal things and practices, though. Recognition of a focal concern must occur through a collective affirmation. That is, by discussing issues openly and at local levels (as well as beyond), society must arrive at a shared understanding of and commitment to a “certain kind of behavior or enterprise” (p. 233). This collective affirmation will allow society to make decisions and accomplish tasks that are beyond the capacities of single individuals. It is at this level that society will be able to recognize trends that need to be either altered or reversed, such as with the kind of potential Kaczynski argues genetic engineering exhibits. Finally, Kaczynski appears to hurt his own argument when he claims that while there is nothing to prevent us from marching out to the wilderness to live primitively, in practice there is very little wild country left. It is wild nature that Kaczynski advocates, within which he includes wild human nature. However, a tension exists in his overall proposal that individuals must break free from technology and live primitively. With so much land already developed to sustain modem society, how is it that Kaczynski can claim individuals must revert back to a primitive lifestyle, when living primitively means living in the wild if one wants to survive? Kaczynski readily admits that very little wild country remains in America, yet he acknowledges that everyone must live close to nature in the face of technological absence.[55] Kaczynski proposes that a period of harsh adjustment will be necessary, but this seems an understatement given the number of people who would be all but forced to sacrifice their lives. Borgmann suggests that living today in a physically sustainable way requires an acceptance of technology, but that this acceptance is the sign of a new maturity. Thus, a notion of wilderness no longer receives respect through its appeal to “wildness.” Rather, the wilderness now moves us deeply in being so fragile and vulnerable, according to Borgmann. Wild nature achieves new and positive significance within the technological setting. A greater respect is what often accompanies this, and it is hoped that these feelings translate into the kind of collective decision-making that promotes the well-being of wild nature and the wilderness. Borgmann would argue that Kaczynski’s notion of the power process can in fact be served in modern society, and in such a way that engages the body and produces feelings offreedom andfulfillment. What is required on the part of the individual is a shift in perspective. Technology must no longer be foregrounded, and focal practices are ways that individuals can push technology to the background of everyday life. Thus, if an individual defines oneself as a runner, a writer, a musician and/or a painter first and foremost, then technology takes on a new meaning. This new meaning, .where technology is backgrounded, is an appreciation for what it has to offer the modem individual. Robert Pirsig also argues that technology can be reconciled with modem society. However, his overall argument is open for criticism when considered alongside Borgmann’s discussion of technology and society. Pirsig declares that it is his intention to ground out a discussion of Quality in the everyday world. As Borgmann (1984) observes, though, Quality takes on such a broad meaning that it loses much of its appeal. Cheney (in press) reveals that the concept “Quality” is a vague one to begin with, one which is conceptualized by today’s organizations not so much as a striving for higher standards of excellence, but merely a direct response to perceived demands. The concept is at once compelling and almost meaningless in contemporary institutions, as no organizations will proclaim themselves to be “anti-quality.” Quality has universal appeal, yet it means almost nothing. In fact, technology itself has become tied up with the abstract value of progress and a pursuit of “the good life,” today more than ever. This connection has permitted technology to be deemed sacred by many. Pirsig argues that physical and mental engagement of the body is the means by which one arrives at Quality, once an understanding of it is achieved, and it is Quality which will present the individual with increased feelings of fulfillment and freedom. However, Pirsig argues that this concept can be applied even at the level of one’s own job. He advocates a return to more of a craftsmanlike approach in one’s work. Borgmann correctly points out that a “Zen-like” approach to all types of jobs simply is not the answer anymore, for specialization has nudged its way into the workforce at many levels. Traditional crafts, and craftsmanship, is what has suffered.. This was the case in the 1970s, and is even more the case today. Borgmann recognizes that innovations can occur only by displacing one form of tradition. Thus, technology had to displace and all but eliminate traditional crafts. The lack of care that Pirsig argues is present in things like jobs is perhaps only partly due to a change in values. The specialization of labor that has developed is a consideration Pirsig does not address. Quality does appear to possess some similarities to Borgmann’s discussion of the focal practice. Borgmann discusses an “excellence” that is at the heart of many pursuits, and Quality as Pirsig references it can be argued to translate to excellence. Both discussions also tie nicely into Csikszentmihalyi’s (1990) concept of “flow,” which can be characterized as the immersion and enjoyment experienced by the individual who voluntarily applies effort in engaging something difficult and worthwhile. However, the concepts of Quality and the focal practice begin to diverge at the level of application. Pirsig applies Quality not only to all types of jobs, but to endeavors that Borgmann would not characterize as focal practices. Pirsig speaks of the need for engaging his motorcycle, and he argues that he can pursue Quality in maintaining it. This is another example of Pirsig applying the concept of Quality too broadly. In this case, technology is still in the foreground for the individual. Not only is technology utilized in applying what is perceived to be skill, it is the object that the skill is applied toward. This contrasts with the skier, who allows technology to mediate engagement, but engagement is ultimately with the slope.[56] Thus, the skier must exert himself or herself mentally and physically in order to maneuver the slope. Skill is a necessity. One could make the case that no real skill is needed by Pirsig in maintaining the cycle, only a specific knowledge about its form and function. For Pirsig, technology is implicated at the level of both focal practice and focal thing (with the cycle being the focal thing).[57] Again, technology is still in the foreground in Pirsig’s case. Another reason that a “foregrounded” technology is problematic is because it reveals very little about an individual’s surrounding world. For example, Borgmann notes that one might argue that a video game is a focal practice. However, video games usually require a narrow range of skills, and they proceed in “utter indifference to the surrounding world” (p. 215). Conversely, runners and skiers engage roads and mountains, and are in the natural world. Video games not only geographically isolate the individual from the world (when engaged), they also reveal very little about the world in their engagement. This contrasts with writing, which may also be done in isolation, but the difference is that it seeks to illuminate the world around the individual in some way.[58] Essentially, Pirsig applies his concept of Quality too broadly in attempting to reconcile technology with society. Still, one has to wonder about the individual who engages computer programming, or video games, and actually takes the time to learn about the functioning of these things while at the same time attempting to excel at them. If this individual experiences no frustration or alienation from technology (i.e., the problem of technology is virtually nonexistent with him/her), then these endeavors might function in a similar fashion to the focal practice. They may not be the best types of focal practices, but for these individuals they appear to serve this purpose. Finally, Borgmann’s discussion of focal things and practices appears to contribute to Burke’s (1973) notion of “counter nature,” and the potential technology has for allowing the individual to engage it in such a way that a false perception of effort is experienced (e.g., in driving, and the perceived feeling of power individuals can experience when they accelerate by pressing down on the gas pedal). It is easy for individuals to slip into a mindset that they are exerting effort in a given situation, when it is in fact technology which is producing the effort. By adopting a focal concern, the phenomenon of technology is placed in the background of daily life, and it becomes easier for individuals to recognize not only what technology is doing, but what it is doing Tor them. It is implied that the individual will now have a better understanding of this distinction. *** Technology and Society Coping with technology in a way that ensures fulfillment is a challenge for the modem individual. The phenomenon itself looms large in virtually every sphere of life nowadays. The suggestion that technology is omnipresent would not be far from the truth. Moreover, the images of technology that appear in current magazines such as Wired are glamorous and forward-looking, but also cold, in that innovations such as home computers are continually becoming more powerful — at a rate sometimes appearing to be beyond human control). Technology’s seemingly relentless development creates the potential for a more distant relationship with its “pioneers” and users. Commodification and consumption proliferate in an environment where technology and advertising campaigns (among other influences) create persuasive, seductive images of “the good’ life.” These images increasingly consist of newer technologies, such as high-speed gadgets, big-screen televisions, powerful personal computers, etc. It is a genre of discourse (though visual appeals hold.great persuasive power, as well) all to its own — one which embraces commodification and seeks to expand the growing realm of consumption. However, there are ways for the individual to cope with technology that are less extreme than creating a revolution against it. Borgmann’s (1984) discussion of focal things and practices presents the individual with such a method for coping with technology. If individuals can define themselves in ways that place the phenomenon of technology in the background of daily life, concepts like the device paradigm will cease to exist. That is, individuals will no longer feel as though everything about their lives is driven by technology. Rather, technology will be assessed at the level of what it has to offer the individual. Freedom and fulfillment will proliferate, but proper physical and mental engagement of the body may not have to occur through focal practices. In other words, it may be enough for an individual to physically engage his or her body at work, and then rely upon focal practices for mental engagement (e.g., with writing). Thus, the focal practice can produce fulfillment without allowing for significant physical engagement of the body. Focal things and practices contribute to a focal concern, and it is this concern which allows society to address relevant issues of its time. By adopting a focal concern, and arriving at some sort of consensus or list of priorities where issues that affect all of society are concerned, discussion at a “mass” level can lead to decisions about such issues (e.g., the current trend of genetic engineering, and how work in this field should proceed). A focal concern can contribute at the level of the individual (focal things and practices) as well as the societal level (discourse about societal issues). Thus, it is one method of resolving the conflict between the extreme technological deterministic position and the positions which characterize technology either as an unstoppable but positive force, or as nothing more than an innocuous tool. The latter positions are closer to each other in relation than the deterministic position, since they characterize technology more positively. In attempting to resolve the conflict between these positions, technology is seen as a force in its own right (much like the deterministic and “positive force” positions), such as through the device paradigm, and the potential it holds for creating feelings of frustration and alienation from technology in individuals. However, it is a force which can be coped with in modem society. Monitoring the phenomenon of technology and its impact on society must remain an ongoing process. As mentioned, changes as well as shifts in values are worthy issues to probe in researching technology. Also, examining the ways the body is implicated in discussions of technology is certainly relative to a given time period as well as culture. This point appears to justify ongoing examination of the body vis-a-vis technology. Essentially, the phenomenon of technology is one that will remain open for discussion and critique as long as it plays a role in the lives of its “pioneers.” Its role may change shape, but notwithstanding a revolution against its entirety, technology will continue to be a pervasive force in modem society. [1] One such web address is the following: [[http://www.df.lth.se/~micke/wholemanifesto.hfml][http://www.df.lth.se/~micke/wholemanifesto.html]]. The Manifesto can be recovered in full text from other web-sites as well. The page numbers of the Manifesto that get referenced are with respect to its layout from this particular Internet address (pp. 1–52). The site belongs to Mikael G. Niklasson. [2] Technology often gets traced to the ancient Greek techne, which Aristotle characterized as an art concerned with the matter of “making,” not “doing.” This “making” is driven by reason, and the link to technology exists in that technology is in effect the innovative process with a belief based in reason that such innovations will benefit the individual, community, society...etc. See Kennedy (1991) for a discussion of techne as he briefly takes up Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Worthy of mention is Hide’s (1993) discussion of this distinction between “making” and “doing” with respect to techne, and how the “doing” of technology is seen today as more important than the aesthetically determined technology Classical Greece focused upon (see specifically p.26). [3] lam speaking here of modem day society in general, and specifically American society, though other societies across the globe are certainly implicated here as well. [4] By environment I include those natural resources that directly affect the well-being of the human species. There are a growing number of people expressing concern over the natural environment in its own right. However, this is simply meant to emphasize the significance of the technology-environment issue by highlighting the concerns coming to the foreground with most people, not just environmentalists, deep ecologists, eco-feminists...etc. The issue of technology and the environment is the most pressing one involving technology that’s being discussed today. Questions such as: Will there be enough oil in 50 years?, Can we sustain an environment with decent air quality?, and What does the future hold for the Greenhouse Effect and the ozone layer? implicate or are implicated by technology. [5] Pirsig used to teach English/Rhetoric at Montana State University at Bozeman — hence the reference. Interestingly enough, Quality has become a buzzword in the 1980s and 1990s, capable of multiple meanings. It is a slogan in many American organizations today (e.g., Ford Motor Company: “Quality is job one.”). This is not to say that Pirsig has started a “Quality revolution,” but rather just to make an observation. [6] Brian Paul has an interesting site devoted specifically to links about the Unabomber, the Manifesto, or a discussion of the ideas presented in the Manifesto. The address is <[[http://users.andara.com/~bpaul/unabomber.html][http://users.andara.com/~bpaul/unabomber.html]]>. One of the links from the site is an antigovernment page supporting Kaczynski and selling t-shirts which reflect this support (Mendoza, <[[http://www.mayhem.net.Crime/unabombshirts.html][http://www.mayhem.net.Crime/unabombshirts.html]]>). [7] It can be argued that there are in fact three themes to the book: the narrative of the cross-country motorcycle trip, the intellectual framework set forth by the narrator, and the story of Phaedrus. I choose to consider this final component as being a part of one of the previous two, simply because much of the discussion pertaining to Phaedrus is part of either the narrative or the intellectual framework that Pirsig develops, depending on where in the book the reader finds himself or herself. [8] Pirsig gives this character the name Phaedrus because the term was believed to be translated as “lone wolf,” and Pirsig characterizes his former self as a loner — somewhat removed from the rest of society. Pirsig notes in the forward of the 25th anniversary of Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance that this was an error on his part, as the term Phaedrus is in fact more accurately translated as “brilliant” or “radiant.” [9] Pirsig is specifically calling for caring in one’s relationship with technology and its innovations. There is no specific reference in the book to a caring for one another as people. Instead, the emphasis is placed on the individual and the technology that s/he engages. [10] This dichotomy of real or fundamental activities and surrogate or pale substitutes for them is an important one to keep in mind. [11] Kaczynski carries this style throughout his work, whereas Pirsig utilizes a different overall style to correspond with the multiple themes present in his work. This will be discussed in what follows. [12] In fact, one of the first sections (“The Psychology of Modem Leftism”) does not seem to address either specifically, but later gets reintroduced into the discussion when Kaczynski advocates that revolutionaries ought to not associate themselves with this movement, thus falling into the category of strategy, or “how” we ought to respond to the problem. [13] Few people residing in America during the winter of 1973–74 forget about the OPEC oil embargo. [14] For the most part, I am referring to the body in its physical sense. Worthy of mention again is that Pirsig implicates both the physical and mental aspects of the body. Progress needs to be made in both areas, he argues, and the efforts grounded in both aspects of the body serve to illustrate his commitment to a Zen Buddhist philosophy, where striving for oneness is the focus. [15] One can see that the work of Martin and Faludi possesses subtle connections to postmodern theorizing in general and Foucauldian theorizing specifically, by the ways the body gets discussed differently from how society normally discusses it. The difference is that Martin and Faludi outline the ways the body is being reconceptualized through the transformation/development of American society. Foucault takes a more assertive stance in arguing that the ways the body is conceptualized are flawed to begin with, examples being with respect to how human sexuality is conceptualized (1978) and how we discipline ourselves at the both the societal and individual levels (1977). Angela Trethewey (1999) provides such a Foucauldian analysis of the way women’s bodies are conceptualized in the organizational/professional sector, and how they a) choose to discipline their bodies, and b) are expected to discipline their bodies. [16] For examples of other work which focuses on the body in analyzing a text(s), but is unrelated to or less related to a direct examination of the phenomenon of technology, see Houck (1997), Hayden (1998), Kirkmayer (1992), and Culbertson (1995). [17] This is not to say that metaphors involving the body and technology do not exist in the other theme of the book, the intellectual framework Pirsig develops. I will demonstrate that this is also the case. This is merely to make the point that such metaphors are predominantly located in the prior theme, and serve to make the connection of the body and coping with technology between both themes. [18] I use the term “product” in a broad sense, including everything from food to homes. Additionally, while I realize that many societies experience this type of freedom of choice, I also recognize that others simply do not. [19] One such example can be seen in the advent of electronic mail. [20] The terms freedom and autonomy will be defined and/or developed more by Kaczynski later. [21] Kaczynski argues that it is not enough to apply the power process in any manner, but that it must be directed toward real goals (as opposed to surrogate activities). This will be discussed later in this section of the analysis and in even more detail in the “Implicated Body” section. [22] This discussion of biological needs and physical effort will recieve much greater attention in the “Implicated Body” section of my analysis. [23] When I use the term modern man and the masculine follow-up him I am for the most part using Kaczynski’s own words as they appear in the Manifesto. [24] Consider current advances in and prospects for cloning. Additionally, one can examine the progress of the Human Genome Project, and its potential implications. [25] Remember the “drunk with a barrell of wine” analogy? [26] Or control by large organizations, for that matter. [27] Kaczynski also uses the term power frequently in his discussion, but this term is attached to a process (the power process) which he argued was necessary for most individuals to experience.